Skip to main content

Why Legal Rules Are Not Speech Acts and What Follows from That?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule-Following

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 111))

Abstract

The speech-act approach to rules is commonplace in both Anglo-American and continental traditions of legal philosophy. Despite its pervasiveness, I argue in this paper that the approach is misguided and therefore intrinsically flawed. My critique identifies how speech-act theory provides an inadequate theoretical framework for the analysis of written discourse, a case in point being legal text. Two main misconceptions resulting from this misguided approach are the fallacy of synchronicity and the fallacy of a-discursivity. The former consists of treating legal rules as if they were uttered and received in the same context, the latter consists of treating legal rules as relatively short, isolated sentences. Among the consequences of these fallacies are an excessive focus on the lawmakers’ semantic intentions and the neglect of the semantic and pragmatic complexity of rules as sets of utterances (discourses). To redress these flaws, I propose analysing legal rules through the prism of complex text-acts. My paper presents the consequences of this revised approach for legal interpretation, supporting Joseph Raz’s idea of minimal legislative intent.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This applies to both J. L. Austin and J. Searle, and their commentators: K. Bach, R. Harnish and P. Grice, though the latter touches upon communications directed in writing to an unspecified group (cf. e.g. P. Grice’s solution in Studies in the Way of Words devoted to signs such as ‘Keep off the grass’). This analysis is of an auxiliary nature and does not affect the nature of their conclusions. Another exception is the work of Hancher (1979) and Edmondson (1981) on co-operative speech acts, and the work of T. van Dijk on complex speech acts and pragmatic macrostructures (van Dijk 1980). None of these, however, take into account the specifics of writing.

  2. 2.

    It is not the purpose of this paper to determine whether the rules are text acts (or acts in any sense) or if they are the outcomes of such acts.

  3. 3.

    The criticism presented here refers to so called expressive theories of legal norm, i.e. the theories which equate legal norms with linguistic expressions. The critique does not apply to those theories defined as hyletic i.e. those which distinguish between the normative act and the norm as the outcome of this act (and not necessarily a linguistic one). The work of K. Opałek and J. Woleński, can be taken as an example of the latter. I am grateful to the reviewers of this paper for indicating the need to clarify this matter.

  4. 4.

    Distinguishing the fallacy of a-discursivity leads to a question as to the ontological status of a legal rule. This is a version of the question about the individuation of laws (Raz 1980, p. 77).

References

  • Amselek, Paul. 1988. Philosophy of law and the theory of speech acts. Ratio Juris 1 (3): 187–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, John Langshaw. 1962. How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, Claudia. 2014. How to do things with (recorded) words. Philosophical Studies ­167:485–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cao, Deborah. 2007. Legal speech acts as intersubjective communicative actions. In Interpretation, law and the construction of meaning, eds. Anne Wagner, Wouter Werner, and Deborah Cao, 65–82. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cyrul, Wojciech. 2007. Lawmaking. Between discourse and legal text. In Legislation in context. Essays in legisprudence, ed. Luc J. Witgens, 43–54. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edmondson, Willis. 1981. Spoken discourse: A model for analysis. London: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eskridge, Wiliam N. Jr., and Philip J. Frickey. 1990. Statutory interpretation as practical reasoning. Stanford Law Review 42:321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ekins, Richard. 2012. The nature of legislative intent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goffman, Erving. 1981. Forms of talk. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hancher, Michael. 1979. The classification of co-operative illocutionary acts. Language in Society 8 (l): 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L. A. 1958. Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harvard Law Review 71:593–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horner, Winifred B. 1979. Speech-act and text-act theory: “theme-ing” in freshman composition. College Composition and Communication 30 (2): 165–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maley, Yon. 1987. The language of legislation. Language in Society 16:25–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2013. Truth in law. In Law and language. Current legal issues, eds. M. Freeman and F. Smith, vol. 15, 46–47. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ong, Walter Jackson. 2000. Orality and literacy: The technologizing of the word. London: ­Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1980. The concept of the legal system. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 2009a. On the authority and interpretation of constitutions: some preliminaries. In Between authority and interpretation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 2009b. Intention in interpretation. In Between authority and interpretation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin. 1972. Motives, intentions and the interpretation of texts. New Literary History, Vol. 3, No. 2, On Interpretation: I (Winter, 1972) 393–408.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solum, Lawrence. 2008. Semantic originalism. Illinois Public Law and Legal Theory Research Papers Series, Nos. 07–24, Nov 22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stubbs, Michael. 1983. Can I have that in writing? Some neglected topics in speech act theory. Journal of Pragmatics 7:479–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, Teun A. 1980. Macrostructures. An interdisciplinary study of global structures in ­discourse, interaction, and cognition. Hilsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Visconti, Jacqueline. 2009. Speech acts in legal language: introduction. Journal of Pragmatics 41:393–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zieliński, Maciej. 1972. Interpretacja jako proces dekodowania tekstu prawnego. Poznań: Wydawnictwo UAM.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marcin Matczak .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Matczak, M. (2015). Why Legal Rules Are Not Speech Acts and What Follows from That?. In: Araszkiewicz, M., Banaś, P., Gizbert-Studnicki, T., Płeszka, K. (eds) Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule-Following. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 111. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-09375-8_24

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics