Skip to main content

The Ordinary Meaning of Rules

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule-Following

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 111))

Abstract

Judges typically claim that rules contained in legal texts are interpreted in accordance with their ordinary meaning. It follows that the constituent question of what makes some meaning the ordinary one and the evidential question of how the determinants of ordinary meaning are identified and conceptualized are of crucial importance to the interpretation of legal texts. While a comprehensive analysis of these questions is beyond the scope of this chapter, it is possible as well as important to outline how such questions must necessarily be approached. Certainly, there are a variety of ways in which courts habitually go beyond or reject the linguistic meaning of the relevant text. Normatively based desires to, for example, ensure fair notice or avoid constitutional questions may cause a court to give a text a legal meaning that does not correspond with its linguistic meaning. The ordinary meaning principle, though, is necessarily concerned with the linguistic meaning of the text and not normative matters. As such, certain views about meaning and interpretation can be rejected as being incorrect. In particular, certain claims made by actual intentionalists are fundamentally inconsistent with how the ordinary meaning doctrine must be conceptualized. In short, the intentionalist position that a text means what its author intended it to mean, as well as the associated claims about the nature of natural language that often accompany this assertion, must be rejected. Instead, the ordinary meaning doctrine must be explicated on the basis of systematicities and conventions of language.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Taniguchi v. Kan Pacific Saipan Ltd., 132 S.Ct. 1997, 2003 (2012).

  2. 2.

    Of course, not all written language involves a context of interpretation that is far removed from the context of utterance. For example, a note passed in class would involve a context of interpretation that is very similar to the context of utterance.

  3. 3.

    If the speaker uses ‘dried’, as in (1b), the speaker will have said nothing about how the trying came about, though the use of a tea towel, and ‘wiping’ is one possibility.

  4. 4.

    Vagueness could still exist, however, because it is tied more to the nature of language and less to authorial intent. For example, a term is vague if it presents borderline difficulties (Sorensen 1989). Wasow et al. (2005, p. 2) note that “[m]ost expressions in natural languages are vague—that is, the denotations of most expressions are fuzzy around the edges”. When, for example, is something green instead of brown or blue? The answer to the question, whatever it may be, is orthogonal to any concept of ambiguity.

  5. 5.

    “The principle of compositionality states that the meaning of a complex linguistic expression is built up from the meanings of its composite parts in a rule-governed fashion” (Murphy and Koskela 2010, p. 36).

  6. 6.

    For a somewhat similar response to this claim and others by Alexander and Prakash see Sinnott-Armstrong (2005).

  7. 7.

    A distinction between categorical and semantic intentions is irrelevant to most legal texts because there is no doubt as to their proper categorization as legal texts.

  8. 8.

    Such a mistake is not limited to verbal communication. Trivedi (2001) points to an example where a sculptor intended a sculpture to be curvaceous but it instead looks angular.

References

  • Alexander, Larry, and Prakash, Saikrishna. 2003. Mother may I? Imposing mandatory prospective rules of statutory interpretation. Constitutional Commentary 20:97–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Larry, and Prakash, Saikrishna. 2004. Is that English you’re speaking? Why intention free interpretation is an impossibility. San Diego Law Review 41:967–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Azar, Moshe. 2007. Transforming ambiguity into vagueness in legal interpretation. In Interpretation, law and the construction of meaning, eds. A. Wagner, W. Werner, and D. Cao, 121–137. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 2002. Semantic pragmatic. In Meaning and truth, eds. J. Campbell, M. O’Rourke, and D. Shier, 284–292. New York: Seven Bridges.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botne, Robert. 2001. To die across languages: towards a typology of achievement verbs. Linguistic Typology 7:233–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campos, F. Paul. 1996. A text is just a text. Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 19:327–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, Herman. 2007. Semantics and pragmatics: some central issues. In Context-sensitivity and semantic minimalism, eds. Preyer Gerhard and Peter Georg. 3–22. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, Lewis. 1971. Alice’s adventures in wonder-land and through the looking-glass and what alice found there, ed. Green, R. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, Noël. 1992. Art, intention and conversation. In Intention and interpretation, ed. G. iseminger, 117–118. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, Noël. 2011. Art interpretation: The 2010 richard wollheim memorial lecture. British Journal of Aesthetics 51:117–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cruse, D. Alan. 1983. Lexical semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, Stanley. 1989. Doing what comes naturally: change, rhetoric, and the practice of theory in literary and legal studies. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fish, Stanley. 1999.Response: Interpretation is not a theoretical issue. Yale Journal of Law and the Humanities, 11:509–515.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, Stanley. 2005. There is no textualist position. San Diego Law Review 42:629–650.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, Brian. 2010. Revisiting the contribution of literal meaning to legal Meaning. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 30:255–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, Christopher. 2008. Zero tolerance for pragmatics. Synthese 165:359–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldsworthy, Jeffrey. 2005. Moderate versus strong intentionalism: knapp and michaels revisited. San Diego Law Review 42:669–682.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorvett, Jonathan. 2005. Back through the looking glass: On the relationship between intentions and indexicals. Philosophical Studies 124 (3): 295–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenawalt, Kent. 2000. Are mental states relevant for statutory and constitutional interpretation? Cornell Law Review 85:1609–1672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, Mark. 2011a. Legislation as communication? Legal interpretation and the study of linguistic communication. In Philosophical foundations of language in the law, eds. A. Marmor and S. Soames, 217–264. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, Mark. 2011b. The communication theory of legal interpretation and objective notions of communicative intent. Unpublished. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1726524. Accessed 20 Aug 2014.

  • Harris, Roy. 2001. Rethinking writing. New York: Continuum International Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogan, Patrick. 1996. On interpretation: Meaning and inference in law, psychoanalysis, and literature. Athens: University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iseminger, Gary. 1996. Actual intentionalism vs. hypothetical intentionalism. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54 (4): 319–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ivanic, Roz. 1994. Characterizations of context for describing spoken and written discourse. In Writing vs. speaking: language, text, discourse communication: Proceedings of the conference held at the czech language institute of the academy of sciences of the czech REPUBLIC, prague, october, 14–16, 1992, ed. Čmejrková, Světla, Daneš, František and Havlová, Eva, 180–186. Narr Francke Attempto Verlag GmbH & Co. KG.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, Bernard. 1995. Making sense in law: Linguistic, psychological and semiotic Perspectives. Liverpool: Deborah Charles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiefer, Alex. 2005. The Intentional Model of Interpretation. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (3): 271–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knapp, Steven, and Michaels Benn Walter. 1982. Against theory. Critical Inquiry 8 (4): 723–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knapp, Steven, and Michaels Benn Walter. 1987. Against theory 2: Hermeneutics and Deconstruction. Critical Inquiry 14:49–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knapp, Steven, and Michaels Benn Walter. 2005. Not a matter of interpretation. San Diego Law Review 42:651–668.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, Beth, and Rappaport Malka Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Jerrold. 2002. Hypothetical intentionalism: statement, objections, and replies. In Is there a single right interpretation? ed. M. Krausz. 309–318. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Stephen. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Jerrold. 2010. Defending hypothetical intentionalism. British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (2): 139–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manning, John. 2003. The absurdity doctrine. Harvard Law Review 116:2387–2486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2012. Textualism in context. Unpublished manuscript. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2112384. Accessed 20 Aug 2014.

  • Mattila, Heikki. 2002. Comparative Legal Linguistics (Trans. Goddard, C). Burlington: Asgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCubbins, Mathew, and Rodriguez, Daniel. 2011. Deriving interpretive principles from a theory of communication and lawmaking. Brooklyn Law Review 76:979–995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellinkoff, David. 1963. Language of the law. Boston, Massachusetts: Little Brown & Co Law & Business.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravcsik, Edith. 2006. An introduction to syntactic theory. New York: Continuum International Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Lynne, and Anu Koskela. 2010. Key terms in semantics. New York: Continuum International Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, Celeb. 2005. What is textualism? Virginia Law Review 91:347–418.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 360 B.C.E. Phaedrus (Jowett, B., Trans.). http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/phaedrus.html. Accessed 20 Aug 2014.

  • Poggi, Francesca. 2011. Law and conversational implicatures. International Journal for the Semiotics of Law 24:21–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hovav Rappaport Malka, and Beth Levin. 2010. Reflections on manner/result complementarity. In Syntax, lexical semantics, and event structure, eds. Edit Doron, Hovav Malka Rappaport, and Sichel, Ivy, 21–38. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, Michael. 2009. The impossibility of textualism and the pervasiveness of rewriting in law. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 22 (2): 381–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saussure de, Ferdinand. 2011. Course in general linguistics, P. Meisel & H. Saussy (Eds.), trld. W. Baskin. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scalia, Antonin. 1997. A matter of interpretation: Federal courts and the law. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 2005. Word meaning in legal interpretation. San Diego Law Review 42:465–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solan, Lawrence. 2005. Private language, public laws: The central role of legislative intent in statutory interpretation. Georgetown Law Journal 93:427–486.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, Roy. 1989. The ambiguity of vagueness and precision. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 70:174–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stecker, Robert. 2006. Moderate actual intentionalism defended. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (4): 429–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabossi, Patrizia, and Zardon, Francesco. 1993. Processing ambiguous words in context. Journal of Memory and Language 32:359–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tolhurst, William. 1979. On what a text is and how it means. British Journal of Aesthetics 19:3–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trivedi, Saam. 2001. an An epistemic dilemma for actual intentionalism. British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (2): 192–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Berkum, Jos J. A. 2008. Understanding sentences in context: What brain waves can tell us. Current directions in psychological science 17:376–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Berkum, Jos J. A., Danielle, van den Brink, Cathelijne M. J. Y Tesink, Miriam Kos, and Peter Hagoort, 2008. The neural integration of speaker and message. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 20 (4): 580–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Schooten, Hanneke. 2007. Law as fact, law as fiction: A tripartite model of legal communication. In Interpretation, law and the construction of meaning, eds. Wagner Anne, Werner Wouter, and Cao Deborah, 3–20. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • von Savigny, Eike. 1985. An emergence view of linguistic meaning. American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (3): 211–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wasow, Tom, Amy Perfors, and David Beaver. 2005. The puzzle of ambiguity. In Morphology and the web of grammar: essays in memory of Steven G. Lapointe, ed. Orgun C. Orhan and Sells Peter, 1–17. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, George. 1992. Again, theory: on speaker’s meaning, linguistic meaning, and the meaning of a text. Critical Inquiry 19 (1): 164–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, K. William Jr., and C. Monroe Beardsley. 1946. The intentional fallacy. The Sewanee Review 54 (3):468–488.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical investigations. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank the organizers of Rules § 2013 and Jagiellonian University for hosting a terrific conference and the participants for their comments on my paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian G. Slocum PhD .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Slocum, B. (2015). The Ordinary Meaning of Rules. In: Araszkiewicz, M., Banaś, P., Gizbert-Studnicki, T., Płeszka, K. (eds) Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule-Following. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 111. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-09375-8_22

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics