Skip to main content

Inerpretation and Rule Following in Law. The Complexity of Easy Cases

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule-Following

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 111))

Abstract

Lon L. Fuller challenged the positivist distinction between the law “as it is” and the law “as it ought to be” by insisting on the need for interpretation even in easy cases of adjudication. Fuller argued that interpretation is always creative in the light of the purpose of the rule to be applied and thus always draws on the law “as it ought to be”. Andrei Marmor tried to defend positivism against this challenge by advancing the thesis that there is no need for interpretation in easy cases. He drew on Ludwig Wittgenstein’s remarks on rule following to suggest that in easy cases the law is just in need of understanding not of interpretation. Although I also think that positivism can be saved from Fuller’s challenge, I do not think that it can be done with the help of Wittgenstein’s distinction between interpretation and understanding. Fuller’s challenge and Wittgenstein’s remarks on the relation between a rule and its application address different aspects of the process of adjudication in easy cases, which build upon, but which cannot be played out against each other. We have to distinguish between two different elements of our practice of adjudication in easy cases: On the one side the communicative interpretation of utterances—in the case of the law legal texts—in the sense Paul Grice was concerned with; on the other side the application of a rule thus identified as the content of a communicative intention and its application that Wittgenstein’s remarks on rule following are concerned with. Fuller can be understood to have insisted rightly on the ubiquity of the former, which cannot be refuted by any account of the latter. The upshot, though, is not that Fuller’s challenge is successful. Its flaw, however, does not lie in the insistence on the ubiquity of communicative interpretation, but in its exploitation of an ambiguity of the creative element in interpretation, which can designate epistemic and the creativity involved in amending the law via legal construction. In principle only the former is involved in communicative interpretation; only the latter concerns the distinction between the law “as it is” and the law “as it ought to be”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. the similar account of easy cases by Dworkin (1986, p. 353 f).

  2. 2.

    Cf. already Patterson (1996, pp. 86–88), also pitting understanding against interpretation in the constructive sense of Dworkin’s account of easy cases without discussing the role of communicative interpretation.

  3. 3.

    The argument has been picked up for the law by Alexander and Prakash (2004); see also Fish (2008).

  4. 4.

    Cf. the critique of Marmor by Goldsworthy (1995, pp. 457, 462); also Fish (2008, p. 1138).

  5. 5.

    For an excellent explanation of our conceptual problems Keil (2013).

  6. 6.

    On the importance of this insight for the Gettier cases Keil (2013, p. 135 f).

References

  • Alexander, Larry, and Saikrishna Prakash. 2004. Is that english you’re speaking? Why intention free interpretation is an impossibility. San Diego Law Review 41:967–995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making it explicit: Reasoning representing and discursive commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 2002. Tales of the mighty dead: Historical essays in the metaphysics of intentionality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law’s empire. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, Stanley. 2008. Intention is all there is. A critical analysis of Aharon Barak’s purposive interpretation in law. Cardozo Law Review 29:1109–1146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Lon. 1958. Positivism and fidelity to law—a reply to professor Hart. Harvard Law Review 71:630–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, Kathrin. 2009. The normativity of meaning. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, Kathrin, and Åsa Wikforss. 2010. Es braucht die Regel nicht: Wittgenstein on rules and meaning. In The later Wittgenstein on language, ed. Daniel Whiting, 148–166. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldsworthy, Jeffrey. 1995. Marmor on meaning, interpretation, and legislative intention. Legal Theory 1:439–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. 1958. Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harvard Law Review 71:593–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. 1983. Problems of the philosophy of law. In Essays in jurisprudence and philosophy, ed. H. L. A. Hart, 89–119. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Clarendon.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hurd, Heidi. 1989. Sovereignty in silence. Yale Law Journal 99:945–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil, Geert. 2013. Was lehrt uns das Gettier-Problem über das Verhältnis zwischen Intuitionen und Begriffsanalysen? In Das Gettierproblem. Eine Bilanz nach 50 Jahren, ed. Gerhard Ernst and Lisa Marani, 107–144. Münster: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knapp, Steven, and Walter Benn Michaels. 1982. Against theory. Critical Inquiry 8:723–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, Saul. 1982. Wittgenstein on rules and private language: An elementary exposition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2005. Interpretation and legal theory. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Michael S. 1995. Interpreting interpretation. In Law and anterpretation. Essays in legal philosophy, ed. Andrei Marmor, 1–30. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, Dennis. 1996. Law and truth. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, Nathan. 2005. Two conceptions of semantics. In Semantics versus pragmatics, ed. Zoltán Szabó, 317–328. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, Frederick. 1993. Playing by the rules. A philosophical examination of rule-based decision-making in law and in life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 2001. Legislators’ intentions and unintentional legislation. In Law and disagreement, ed. Jeremy Waldron, 119–146. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical investigations. (Trans. Gertrude Anscombe). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zelazo, Philip. 2014. The development of higher-order rule use: Reflection, rule hierarchies, and cognitive control. In This volume,

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

Next to the discussants of the Krakow workshop I thank Dennis Patterson, Giorgio Pino and the members of the Legal Theory Workshop at the European University Institute in Florence (EUI) for their comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ralf Poscher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Poscher, R. (2015). Inerpretation and Rule Following in Law. The Complexity of Easy Cases. In: Araszkiewicz, M., Banaś, P., Gizbert-Studnicki, T., Płeszka, K. (eds) Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule-Following. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 111. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-09375-8_21

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics