Skip to main content

Fact, Fiction, and Social Reality in Roman Law

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Legal Fictions in Theory and Practice

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 110))

Abstract

Roman and civil law fictions were notorious among early modern critics for their variety and scope. The unborn are treated as living; the living are treated as dead; aliens are classified as citizens; clauses in legal instruments are assumed not to have been written. The essay surveys fictions in classical Roman law, both those the Romans themselves labeled fictions and others that functioned through similar linguistic operations. Particular attention is given to the use of fictions in practice, both in statute and surviving legal instruments. Finally, the essay explores the theoretical frameworks within which Romans understood the operation of fictions, especially the distinction between social and legal facts and the natural and the imaginary.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On Bentham see Stolzenberg (1999) and the essays by Michael Lobban and Michael Quinn (Chaps. 4 and 10) in this volume. Romanists on Roman legal fictions: Richardson (1995), Thomas (1995), Bianchi (1997), Ando (2011b, pp. 1–18, 115–131), and Cornu Thénard (2011). Roman fictions within comparative projects: Maine (1861, pp. 13–25), Gray (1909, pp. 30–38), Fuller (1930/1931, pp. 373, 378, 389–390, 521–523, 545), Knauer (2010), see also Eden (1986, pp. 45–48), Moscovitz (2003).

  2. 2.

    For a description of the constitution of the text of the Institutes, see Schiller (1978, pp. 43–46). The break falls between Chaps. 31 and 32 of book 4: see de Zulueta (1946, pp. 244–246). The only other extended treatment directed to fictions as a general topic rather than the operation of a particular fiction occurs in a rhetorical handbook of the first century CE. There, the author is concerned with suppositions made by parties to the dispute in pleading: “It seems appropriate to add that arguments may be developed not only on the basis of agreed upon facts but also from fictitious supposition, which the Greeks call καθ᾿ ὑπόθεσιν ( kath’ hypothesin), ‘hypothetical.’ This is true of all the types of argument listed above, since there as many species based on fiction as on truth. To suppose a fiction means, in this context, either to put forward something that, if true, would either destroy or strengthen the point raised or to make the matter under dispute appear similar to one’s fiction” (Quintilian, Institutio Oratoria 5.10.95-96 = Russell (2001, pp. 414–415)).

  3. 3.

    Gaius Institutes 4.32 = de Zulueta (1946, p. 246).

  4. 4.

    The text of the Roman law governing the farming of customs duties in the Roman province of Asia was discovered in 1976 and fully published in 1989; Cottier et al. (2008) presents an updated edition of the Greek text and an English translation. The text dates from 62 CE but the form of the text reveals that much of its content was tralatician, passed down, despite periodic revision, all the way from its first enactment late in the second or early in the first century BCE. On this aspect of its character see Ando, Roman Social Imaginaries, Chap. 3.

  5. 5.

    In one problematic but classic formulation, the Praetor created new legal actions “by imitating proper law” (Gaius Institutes 4.111 = de Zulueata (1946, pp. 276–277): Gaius here describes a special case but the particularities do not merit discussion in this context). On the development of Praetorian law see Frier (1985); for an old-fashioned, formalist account see Jolowicz and Nicholas (1972, pp. 191–199). Maine likewise characterizes the use of fictions in England as effecting the “extension, modification and improvement of law” (1865, p. 18).

  6. 6.

    For an account of legal legitimacy at Rome along these lines see Ando (2011b, pp. 4–11).

  7. 7.

    Gaius Institutes 4.34–38 = de Zulueta (1946, pp. 246–249).

  8. 8.

    Cf. Hermogenianus bk. 2 Iuris Epitomarum fr. 54 Lenel = Dig. 27.1.41. On this text see further Ando, Roman Social Imaginaries, Chap. 2.

  9. 9.

    Ulpian [Ad legem Iuliam] de adulteriis bk. 2 fr. 1949 Lenel = Dig. 48.5.16.3.

  10. 10.

    Here one might make a cautious and limited comparison to the apparently non-controversial nature of fictions in Rabbinic law, on which see Leib Moscovitz’s Chap. 15 in this volume.

  11. 11.

    Ando (2014a).

  12. 12.

    Of course, it was possible in theory for a later praetor to remove formulae from the published list of available legal actions, just as he might add ones, but it seems quite clear that the vast bulk of the content of the Praetor’s edict (as the list of formulae was known) was tralatician. Far the best guide to this material remains Lenel (1927).

  13. 13.

    On the distinction between issues of fact and issues of law supposed by this scheme see Cornu Thénard 2012.

  14. 14.

    Fuller (1930/1931, p. 390), following Gray (1909, p. 31). As my engagement here is with Gray and Fuller over their characterization of Roman evidence, I do not entertain the broader question whether their characterization of fictions (whether via Vaihinger or Ross or some other theorist) is sufficient: on that topic see Kelsen (Chap. 1) and Stern (Chap. 8) in this volume.

  15. 15.

    Fuller (1930/1931), pp. 390–391.

  16. 16.

    We are thus in the vicinity of a fact “posed but not affirmed,” on which see Ross (1969, p. 231), with the reading of him in Stern, this volume, Chap. 8.

  17. 17.

    Birks (1986, esp. pp. 94–99); compare Fuller on what he calls “Fictitious Legal Relations,” perhaps the weakest part of his essays (1930/1931, pp. 383–384). In his chapter in this volume, Stern urges that legal fictions can be distinguished from metaphors as a matter of both form and intent, fictions being employed in such a way that all parties understand the limited purpose and effect of the operation; but he also suggests that further study is needed in order to assess how the audiences of legal fictions understood and elaborated upon the fictitious facts in question. I have made a limited gesture in this direction regarding the regular employment of fictions assimilating aliens to Romans (2011b, pp. 10–11).

  18. 18.

    Gaius Institutes 4.37, translation in de Zulueta (1946, p. 249).

  19. 19.

    Compare RS text no. 63, the Lex Quinctia on aqueducts. An initial clause concerns the punishment to be imposed for “holing or fracturing” an underground conduit. A later clause treats disregard for the boundary stones that demarcate the materials and right-of-way of the water system, and concludes: “Whoever shall have done anything contrary to these rules, against him statute, law and position in all matters and for all <---> are to be exactly the same as it would be or it would be appropriate for it to be, if he contrary to this statute had fractured or holed an underground conduit” (see esp. lines 30–31: siremps lex ius causaque omnium rerum omnibusque <---> esto atque uti esset essve oporteret …).

  20. 20.

    The bronze tablet from Contrebia received a magnificent first edition from John Richardson, which was followed immediately by an exemplary exploration by Birks, Rodger and Richardson of the legal issues that it raises: Richardson (1983); Birks et al. (1984). My esteem for those publications notwithstanding, I dissent from the interpretation of the fiction on which they settle (Birks et al. (1984, pp. 52–54)). The details are irrelevant to the status of the fiction in argument and so I set them aside here.

  21. 21.

    I will explore this use of pro further below. For its range of meaning see OLD s.v. pro 6, 8 and 9. On Roman terminology for, and conceptualizations of, the usurpation of citizenship see the Conclusion to Ando, Roman Social Imaginaries.

  22. 22.

    Gaius Institutes 4.103–105 = de Zulueta (1946, pp. 274–277).

  23. 23.

    Cicero In Verrem 2.2.32; for a text and facing translation see Greenwood (1928, pp. 326–327).

  24. 24.

    See Ando (2014b, Sect. 14.3) and idem, Legal Pluralism.

  25. 25.

    Relevant at least are RS texts no. 6, 15, 16, 17, 24, 28 and 29.

  26. 26.

    See RS no. 16, ll. 4–5; RS no. 17, ll. 3; RS no. 18, l. 7; RS no. 24, l.83; RS no. 28, col. 2, ll. 54–55.

  27. 27.

    RS no. 16, l. 11; RS no. 17, l. 15; RS no. 24, l.83; RS no. 28, col. 2, ll. 54–55.

  28. 28.

    RS no. 16, line 6.

  29. 29.

    RS no. 17, ll. 16–17 (the text is defective, but the sense seems clear).

  30. 30.

    RS no. 28, Chap. 20, Col. I, ll. 21–31.

  31. 31.

    RS no. 28, Chap. XXII, ll. 40–43 (see also ll. 45–40): siremps lex res ius caussaque omnibus omnium rerum esto, atque utei esset esseve oporteret sei is … de ieis rebus Romae apud praetorem eumve quei de ieis rebus Romae iure deicundo praeesset in iure confessus esset …

  32. 32.

    Roman jurisdictional fictions thus blur the distinction drawn by Michael Lobban in his Chap. 10 (this volume) between procedural and metaphysical fictions, in the sense that they rendered matters justiciable by Roman courts using Roman procedure, but they also accomplished this by taking as fact things that had not happened or did not exist as supposed.

  33. 33.

    Lex Flavia municipalis Chap. 91 = González (1986, p. 179 [Latin], p. 198 [English]).

  34. 34.

    Thus, although Roman jurists did employ fictions in explantory roles of the sort described by Michael Lobban in this volume, Chap. 10, I treat many of these as heuristic, to wit, as revealing the operation of fictions in the statutes under study.

  35. 35.

    For a summary of views on the so-called curiate law see Gizewski (2003).

  36. 36.

    Cicero, Contra Rullum 2.29 = Clark (1909, p. 139), on which see Ando (2011b, pp. 7–8).

  37. 37.

    In constitutional terms, what Rullus envisaged, which Cicero elsewhere approved, was the dismantling of constitutional procedures-cum-safeguards through the implicit ascription of power to the popular assembly or, if you will, to the People as sovereign to create new constitutional realities by legislative enactment, regardless of earlier practice or even of earlier constraints the People had voted upon itself. For a reading of this text along these lines see Ando (2013).

  38. 38.

    I adapt the edition and translation of Adamik (2003).

  39. 39.

    Livy 22.10.2-6 = Walters and Conway (1929, ad loc.). This text was the object of an extraordinary article by the historian of religion Arthur Darby Nock (1939), which is reprinted with introduction and translations of all Greek and Latin texts in Ando (2003, pp. 84–97).

  40. 40.

    The material below adapts arguments first made in Ando (2013, pp. 922–924). Those pages were in turn inspired by Richardson (1995, pp. 122–123).

  41. 41.

    OLD s.v.; Lewis and Short (1879, s.v.).

  42. 42.

    As a related matter, grants of honorific titles or honorary membership in corporate bodies usually declare only the fact of the grant, but occasionally the logic is spelled out. See, e.g., a decree of the city council of Veii from 26 CE: Gaius Julius Gelon “should be considered [to be] among the number of the Augustales exactly as if he had held that honor …” (Dessau (1906, pp. 624–625), text no. 6579). On such grants see Melchor Gil and Rodríguez Neila (2012).

  43. 43.

    Livy 8.23.10–12 = Walters and Conway (1919, p. 180), on which passage see Oakley (1998, pp. 658–661). See also Livy 10.22.9 = Walters and Conway (1919, p. 340).

  44. 44.

    Fasti triumphales capitolini year 326 b.c.e. = a.u.c. 428 = Degrassi (1947, pp. 70–71).

  45. 45.

    For another case in which ancient sources draw an equivalence between the use of pro to strike an equivalence and a more explicitly fictional operand see n. 69.

  46. 46.

    Cf. Isidore, Etymologiae 9.3.8 = Lindsay (1911, p. 363): Proconsules suffecti erant consulibus, et dicti proconsules eo quod vicem consulis fungerentur, sicut procurator curatori, id est actori, which is translated in Barney et al. (2006, p. 200) as follows: “Proconsuls were substitutes for consuls, and were called proconsuls because they would function in the place of consuls, as a procurator does in the place of curator, that is, an agent.”

  47. 47.

    Livy 38.42.8–10 = Walsh (1999, p. 184); the crucial contrast is drawn in the last sentence: Si exercitus in his terris esse placeat, consules iis potius quam priuatos praeesse oportere.

  48. 48.

    TLL s.v. “proconsul” = vol. 10, fasc. 2 (1998), p. 1542 line 17—p. 1545 line 58 (Hadjú).

  49. 49.

    Sherk (1969), document no. 61, line 12, a governor’s edict from 27 BCE inscribed at Cyme: Vinicius proconsul salutem dat magistratibus Cumas. Regarding the late Republican evidence that I here set aside see Ando (2013, pp. 922–924).

  50. 50.

    For a study of Roman institutions along these lines see Ando, Roman Social Imaginaries, Chap. 2.

  51. 51.

    Lex agraria ( RS 2) ll. 29–31, on which see Ando (2011b, pp. 119–120).

  52. 52.

    Lex agraria (RS 2), ll. 31 and 66.

  53. 53.

    One might clarify the stakes in such assimilations by examining a case of fraud, to explain which the extant record employs a similar assimilation. According to Valerius Maximus, Gaius Visellius Varro was having an affair with Otacilia, a married woman. Falling ill and fearing death, Varro recorded a false loan to himself from Otacilia in the amount of 300,000. According to the explanation of Valerius Maximus, his was plan was that if he should die, she could claim the sum from his heirs, which he wanted to be legati genus, “a kind of legacy” (Valerius Maximus 8.2.2 = Briscoe (1998, pp. 508–509)). Compare the language used by Paul to assimilate a good-faith possessor of land to its owner in respect of their ownership of its fruit, against the specificities of statute: “in all things that pertain to its fruit, [the good-faith possessor] is practically in the place of its owner” (quia quod ad fructus attinet, loco domini paene est) (Paulus Ad Plautium bk. 7 frag. 1140 = Dig. 41.1.48.pr.). Many uses of quasi should be understood along these lines, on which see Ando, Roman Social Imaginaries, Chap. 2.

  54. 54.

    Gaius Inst. 2.5-7a = de Zulueta (1949, pp. 66–67).

  55. 55.

    Servius ad Aen. 2.116 = Thilo and Hagen (1881, p. 238).

  56. 56.

    Dig. 50.17.207.

  57. 57.

    Ulpian Lex Iulia et Papia bk. 1 frag. 1978 Lenel = Dig. 1.5.25 (also, in part, 50.17.207) & Dig. 40.16.4 & Dig. 40.10.6.

  58. 58.

    The use of the term natura, “nature,” to mean “reality” or even “social reality” is the subject of an extraordinary essay by Yan Thomas (1991), closely related to his work on fiction.

  59. 59.

    Gaius Inst. 3.194 = de Zulueta (1946, pp. 216–217).

  60. 60.

    These acts of imagination should be read in light of Simon Stern’s Chap. 8: (this volume) they should perhaps be taken as a riposte to any easy assumption that legal fictions always foreclose the generative effects that analogy or simile promote (to paraphrase Stern).

  61. 61.

    Gaius Inst. 3.56, 3.58 =de Zulueta (1946, pp. 166–169). On Roman law of slavery see Buckland (1908).

  62. 62.

    Papinian Definitiones bk. 2 frag. 46 Lenel = Dig. 1.1.7.1.

  63. 63.

    Gaius Inst. 3.56.

  64. 64.

    For extra-legal evidence for Augustus’s worries regarding the purity of the citizen body see Cassius Dio 56.33.1-3 = Cary (1924, pp. 72–75), on which see Swan (2004, pp. 316–317), though I am not so pessimistic about the reliability of this passage as some of those whose views are summarized by Swan.

  65. 65.

    On Latin as a legal status see Oakley (1998, pp. 538–542, 567–568) and Kremer (2006).

  66. 66.

    Gaius Inst. 3.55–56 = de Zulueta (1946, pp. 166–169).

  67. 67.

    Gaius 3.56 = de Zulueta (1946, pp. 166–167).

  68. 68.

    One might compare the arguments elaborated by jurists about invalid or impossible conditions in wills and testaments: these must be regarded as never have been written–pro non scripto–for the will to possess validity (see, exempli gratia, Dig. 28.7.20 or 29.7.2.1). The language of scholarship consolidates elsewhere around fiction: for a codicil to function as a testament, for example, their contents must be regarded perinde ac si, exactly as if they had been written in a will (again, exempli gratia, see Dig. 29.7.2.2; 29.7.14).

  69. 69.

    Further problems arose when a Junian Latin received Roman citizenship, which he might do by one of several procedures. On this contingency see Gaius Inst. 3.72–73 = de Zulueta (1946, pp. 172–175). Note the contortions that produce, and are produced by, the case where “a Roman citizen freedman dies a Latin …”.

  70. 70.

    Paul Ad legem Falcidiam frag. 921 Lenel = Dig. 35.2.1.1. Compare Julian Digest bk. 62 frag. 759 Lenel = Dig. 28.6.28.

  71. 71.

    Paul Quaestiones bk. 11 frag. 1373 Lenel = Dig. 35.2.18.pr.

  72. 72.

    Paul Quaestiones bk. 11 frag. 1373 Lenel = Dig. 35.2.18.pr.

  73. 73.

    For an argument along these lines see Ando, Roman Social Imaginaries, Chap. 3.

  74. 74.

    Cicero, Paradoxa Stoicorum 31 = Rackham (1942, pp. 282–283).

References

  • Adamik, Tamás. 2003. Temple regulations from Furfo (CIL I2 756). In Latin vulgaire—latin tardif VI, eds. Heikki Solin, Martti Leiwo, and Hilla Halla-aho, 77–82. Hildesheim: Olms-Weidmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ando, Clifford, ed. 2003. Roman religion. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ando, Clifford. 2011a. Law and the landscape of empire. In Figures d’empire, fragments de mémoire: Pouvoirs (pratiques et discours, images et représentations), et identités (sociales et religeuses) dans le monde romain impérial (I er s. av. J.-C.—V e s. ap. J.C.), eds. Stéphane Benoist, Anne Daguey-Gagey, and Christine Hoët-van Cauwenberghe, 25–47. Paris: Presses Universitaires de Septentrion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ando, Clifford. 2011b. Law, language and empire in the Roman tradition. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ando, Clifford. 2013. The origins and import of republican constitutionalism. Cardozo Law Review 34:917–935.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ando, Clifford. 2014a. Exemplum, analogy and precedent in Roman law. In Between exemplarity and singularity: Literature, philosophy, law, eds. Michèle Lowrie and Susanne Lüdemann. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ando, Clifford. 2014b. Pluralism and empire, from Rome to Robert cover. Critical Analysis of Law 1:1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ando, Clifford. In progress. Legal pluralism in practice. In The Oxford handbook of Roman law and society, ed. Clifford Ando, Paul du Plessis and Kaius Tuori. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ando, Clifford. Forthcoming. Roman social imaginaries. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barney, Stephen A., W. J. Lewis, J. A. Beach, and Oliver Berghof. 2006. The etymologies of Isidore of Seville. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (trans.)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Back-Walter = Hans Beck, and Uwe Walter, eds. 2004. Die Frühen Römischen Historiker. 2 vols. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, Ernesto. 1997. Fictio iuris: ricerche sulla finzione in diritto romano dal periodo arcaico all’epoca augustea. Padova: CEDAM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birks, Peter. 1986. Fictions ancient and modern. In The legal mind: Essays for Tony Honoré, eds. Neil MacCormick and Peter Birks, 83–101. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birks, P., A. Rodger, and J. S. Richardson. 1984. Further aspects of the Tabula Contrebiensis. Journal of Roman Studies 74:45–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, John. 1998. Valeri Maximi Facta et Dicta Memorabilia, Volume II: Libri VII–IX. Stuttgart: Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckland, W. W. 1908. The Roman law of slavery. The condition of the slave in private law from Augustus to Justinian. Cambridge: The University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cary, Earnest. 1924. Dio’s Roman history. Volume 7: Books LVI–LX. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Albert. 1909. M. Tulli Ciceronis Orationes, Volume IV: Pro P. Quinctio …. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornu Thénard, Nicolas. 2011. La notion de fait dans la jurisprudence classique. Étude sur les principes de la distinction entre fait et droit. PhD. thesis, Université de Paris 2. A monographic version of this text will be published in 2014 by Editions de Boccard, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornu Thénard, Nicolas. 2012. Le duel entre fait et droit chez les juristes classiques. In Carmina iuris. Mélanges en l’honneur de Michel Humbert, eds. E. Chevreau, D. Kremer, and A. Laquerrière-Lacroix, 191–205. Paris: De Boccard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cottier, M., M. H. Crawford, C. V. Crowther, J.-L. Ferrary, B. M. Levick, O. Salomies, and M. Wörrle, eds. 2008. The customs law of Asia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Degrassi, Attilio, ed. 1947. Inscriptiones Italiae. 13 vol. fasc. 1. Rome: La Libreria dello Stato.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dessau, Hermann. 1906. Inscriptiones Latinae Selectae. 2 vol, part 1. Berlin: Weidmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eden, Kathy. 1986. Poetic and legal fiction in the Aristotelian tradition. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frier, Bruce W. 1985. The rise of the Roman jurists. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L. L. 1930/1931. Legal fictions. Illinois Law Review 25:363–99, 513–546, 877–910.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gizewski, Christian. 2003. Curiata lex. In Brill’s new pauly, eds. Hubert Cancik and Helmuth Schneider, 1014. 3 vols. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • González, Julián. 1986. The lex irnitana: a new Flavian municipal law. Journal of Roman Studies 76:147–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, John Chipman. 1909. The nature and sources of the law. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenwood, L. H. G. 1928. Cicero VII. The verrine orations I. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hans Kelsen. 2014. On the theory of juridic fictions. With special consideration of Vaihinger’s Philosophy of the as-if. In Legal fictions in theory and practice, ed. Maksymilian Del Mar and William Twining. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jolowicz, H. F., and Barry Nicholas. 1972. Historical introduction to the study of Roman Law. 3rd ed. Cambrige: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knauer, Nancy J. 2010. Legal fictions and juristic truth. St. Thomas Law Review 23:1–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kremer, David. 2006. Ius Latinum. Le concept de droit latin sous la République et l’Empire. Romanité et modernité du droit. Paris: de Boccard; Rome: École française de Rome.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenel, Otto. 1927. Das Edictum Perpetuum. Ein Versuch seiner Wiederhestellung. 3rd ed. Leipzig: Tauchnitz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, Charlton T., and Charles Short. 1879. A new latin dictionary, founded on the translation of Freund’s Latin-German Lexikcon edited by E. A. Andrews, LL.D. New York: Harper & Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay, W. M. 1911. Isidori hispalensis episcopi etymologiarum sive originum libri XX. Tomus I Libros I-X continens. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lobban, Michael. 2014. Legal fictions before the age of reform. In Legal fictions in theory and practice, ed. Maksymilian Del Mar and William Twining. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maine, Henry Sumner. 1861. Ancient law. London: J.M. Dent & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melchor Gil, Enrique, and Juan Francisco, Rodríguez Neila. 2012. La integración real o ficticia en los ordines decurionum: lecti, cooptati, adlecti y ornamentarii. Epigraphica 74:109–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moscovitz, Leib. 2003. Legal fictions in rabbinic law and Roman law: Some comparative observations. In Rabbinic law and its near eastern context, ed. Catherine Hezser, 105–132. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moscovitz, Leib. 2014. Rabbinic legal fictions. In Legal fictions in theory and practice, ed. Maksymilian Del Mar and William Twining. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nock, A. D. 1939. A feature of Roman religion. Harvard Theological Review 32:83–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oakley, S. P. 1998. A commentary on livy books VI–X. Volume II: Books VII and VIII. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • OLD = Glare, P. G. W., ed. 1982. Oxford latin dictionary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, Michael. 2014. Fuller on legal fictions: A benthamic perspective. In Legal fictions in theory and practice, ed. Maksymilian Del Mar and William Twining. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rackham, H. 1942. Cicero De Oratore Book III. De Fato. Paradoxa Stoicorum. De Partitione Oratoria. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, J. S. 1983. The Tabula contrebiensis: Roman law in Spain in the early first century b.c. Journal of Roman Studies 73:33–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, J. S. 1995. The Roman mind and the power of fiction. In The passionate intellect: Essays on the transformation of classical traditions presented to Professor I.G. Kidd, ed. L. Ayres, 117–130. Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities 7. New Brunswick: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, Alf. 1969. Legal fictions. In Law, reason, and justice, ed. Graham Hughes, 217–234. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • RS = Crawford, Michael. ed. 1996. Roman statutes. 2 vols. London: Institute of Classical Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Donald A. 2001. Quintilian: The orator’s education. 2 vol. Books 3–5. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiller, A. Arthur. 1978. Roman law. Mechanisms of development. New York: Mouton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sherk, R. K., ed. 1969. Roman documents from the Greek east: Senatus consulta and Epistulae to the death of Augustus. Baltimore: John Hopkins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, Simon. 2014. Legal fictions and exclusionary rules. In Legal fictions in theory and practice, ed. Maksymilian Del Mar and William Twining. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stolzenberg, Nomi Maya. 1999. Bentham’s theory of fictions. A “Curious double language.” Cardozo Studies in Law and Literature 11:223–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swan, Peter Michael. 2004. The Augustan succession. An historical commentary on Cassius Dio’s Roman history books 55–56 (9 BC—AD 14). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thilo, Georg, and Hermann Hagen, eds. 1881. Servii Grammatici qui feruntur in Vergilii carmina commentarii, Volume 1: Aeneidos Librorum I-V commentarii. Leipzig: Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, Yan. 1991. Imago naturae. L’institution de la nature. In Théologie et droit dans la formation de l’Etat moderne, 241–278. Rome: École Française de Rome.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, Yan. 1995. Fictio legis. L’empire de la fiction romaine, 17–63. 21 vol. Droits: revue française de théorie juridique.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, Yan. 1996. “Origine” et “commune patrie.” Étude de droit public romain (89 av. J.-C.—212 ap. J.C.). Rome: École Française de Rome.

    Google Scholar 

  • TLL = Thesaurus Linguae Latinae. 1904. Leipzig: Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, P. G. 1999. Titi Livi Ab Urbe Condita. Tomus VI. Libri XXXVI–XL. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walters, Charles Flamstead, and Robert Seymour, Conway, eds. 1919. Titi Livi Ab Urbe Condite, Volume 2: Libri VI–X. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walters, Charles Flamstead, and Robert Seymour, Conway, eds. 1929. Titi Livi Ab Urbe Condita, Volume 3: Libri XXI–XXV. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Zulueta, Francis. 1946. The Institutes of Gaius. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Clifford Ando .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Conclusion

Conclusion

Fictions performed heroic labor in Roman law . In part this came about because of historic change of two kinds. The first change was the creation of a new source of law in the early second century BCE, to wit, the granting to the praetor of not merely the power to hear cases but to create new legal actions. This power was rapidly understood as sufficient to create work-arounds to statute law. Friction of various kinds at the level of procedure and substance between statute and praetorian law was often negotiated by means of operations the Romans deemed fictions but which can to a point be described as analogical: two situations were construed as similar, and a symmetry of consequence was ordered to exist between the two.

The second change driving the use of fictions was the expansion of the empire. The rapid embrasure of new territories demanded the reduplication of institutions of governance, including both magistracy and jurisdiction. Often (though not always), this need was met by fiction: private individuals were invested with magisterial power without the formality of an election, and cases between aliens before local magistrates on alien soil were conditionally imagined as being lodged between Roman citizens and heard by a Roman magistrate, presiding over the case in the city of Rome.

The fictional nature of these operations is not always superficially apparent. Substitutions were made, equivalences struck and third-person imperatives deployed without being flagged as fictional or marked by contrafactuals. Often enough, however, they can be detected because an ancient commentator provides an interpretive gloss on the lexical apparatus that unpacks the fiction at work in its operation.

These fictions thus constitute a special case of legal change, of the sort so ably described by Maks Del Mar in this volume (see Chap. 11). For one thing, the form of social change that drove legal change was specific to empire. It was not simply expansion of the state, but the ever present need to account for social, economic and ecological realities scarcely imagined in the heyday of Roman legislation and conducted in languages other than its own. And for another, Roman fictions went nearly wholly uncontested. This may have occurred because they were felt to be conservative in intent (as Maine, Fuller and others suggest, which position I have to a point endorsed). It may also have occurred because of some wider endorsement of the constructivist power of legal language , of which the early use of third-person imperatives in the vow of the Sacred Spring and the late reflection of Ulpian on res iudicatae are but tips of an iceberg.Footnote 72 It is nonetheless tempting to observe that the assimilation of things outside some normative taxonomy to items inside (as Gaius did in respect to sacred and religious land) is conservative in the same way that gay marriage is conservative: the hitherto illicit is hereafter recognized only at the expense of its assimilation to preexisting standards of (hetero)normativity. Understood in these terms, many Roman fictions were acts of power, that governed indigenous realities by re-imagining them in Roman garb.

However intended, fictions also threatened the stability of existing social ontologies. This power is certainly latent in those operations of law whereby social facts of considerable ideological importance, like servile status or descent from slaves, were bracketed or betimes rewritten. And it was occasionally (re)marked, as when Ulpian felt and flagged the insufficiency of some cohomology between legal principle, social principle and normative language , caused not least by an epistemic weakness in the conditions of judgment whose status as structural haunted the Roman (legal) imagination.

That said, the abiding impression left by Roman texts is of a constructivism, or nominalism, if you will, of surpassing power. Consider in closing Cicero’s claim in regard to people sentenced to exile who do not leave the city and, in remaining resident, might seem to violate a principle material condition of the ontology of exile: “All criminal and imperious people whom the laws want to be punished with exile are exiles, even if they do not exchange [Roman for alien] soil.”Footnote 73

Acknowledgements

My thanks to Maksymilian Del Mar and William Twining for the invitation to participate in this project.

Note Dig. = Alan Watson, ed., The Digest of Justinian, 4 volumes (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1985). The Digest will be cited by book, chapter, and paragraph number. Lenel = Otto Lenel, Palingenesia Iuris Civilis (Leipzig: Tauchnitz, 1889). Fragments from Lenel will be cited by author, book title, and fragment number.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ando, C. (2015). Fact, Fiction, and Social Reality in Roman Law. In: Del Mar, M., Twining, W. (eds) Legal Fictions in Theory and Practice. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 110. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-09232-4_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics