Advertisement

Moral Strata pp 133-168 | Cite as

Securing Our Moral Ends

  • John R. WelchEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Theory and Decision Library A: book series (TDLA, volume 49)

Abstract

Chapter 5 concentrates on the teleological stratum of moral discourse. The ends of Kantian, Benthamite, and Frankenian moral theories are the good will, the greatest happiness of the greatest number, and beneficence with justice respectively. Since each of these ends can generate moral advice that differs from that of the others, the relative merits of these ends is a fundamental moral issue. Is there any rational way to choose among them? This chapter argues for an affirmative answer. When ends are expressed in teleological descriptions such as ‘The highest good is the greatest happiness of the greatest number’, the descriptions can be viewed as hypotheses and thereby confirmed or disconfirmed through hypothetico-deductive reasoning analogous to that employed in the sciences. But when ends are expressed in teleological directives such as ‘Act with a good will’, choice among directives can be reasonably guided by the comparative decision theory of Chap. 3. Finally, the chapter addresses the higher-order end of morality itself: Can the aim of acting morally be rationally justified? The chapter urges that coherence requires the adoption of ‘I ought to be moral’ and that coherence in turn can be justified.

Keywords

Decision Theory Reflective Equilibrium Moral Discourse Modus Tollens Great Happiness 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Allais, Maurice. 1953. Fondements d’une théorie positive des choix comportant un risque et critique des postulats et axiomes de l’école américaine. Econometrie 40:257–332. English edition: Allais, Maurice. 1979. The foundations of a positive theory of choice involving risk and a criticism of the postulates and axioms of the American school. In Expected utility hypotheses and the Allais paradox: Contemporary discussions of decisions under uncertainty with Allais’ rejoinder, ed. Maurice Allais and Ole Hagen, 27–145. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  2. Alston, William P. 1993. Epistemic desiderata. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53:527–551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Angere, Staffan. 2007. The defeasible nature of coherentist justification. Synthese 157:321–335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Angere, Staffan. 2008. Coherence as a heuristic. Mind 117:1–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Atkinson, David, Jeanne Peijnenburg, and Theo Kuipers. 2009. How to confirm the conjunction of disconfirmed hypotheses. Philosophy of Science 87:1–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Audi, Robert. 1989. Practical reasoning. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  7. Audi, Robert. 2001. The architecture of reason: The structure and substance of rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. BonJour, Laurence. 1998. Knowledge and justification, coherence theory of. In Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E. Craig. London: Routledge. http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/P009. Accessed 30 April 2014.
  9. Bovens, Luc, and Stephan Hartmann. 2003. Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Braybrooke, David. 1987. Social contract theory’s fanciest flight. Ethics 97:750–764.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Carnap, Rudolf. 1962. Logical foundations of probability. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  12. Conee, Earl, and Richard Feldman. 2010. In A companion to epistemology, ed. Jonathan Dancy, Ernest Sosa, and Matthias Steup, 2nd ed., 123–130. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. Dewey, John. 1910. How we think. Lexington: D. C. Heath.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Dewey, John. 1922. Human nature and conduct: An introduction to social psychology. In The middle works, 1899–1924, eds. Jo Ann Boydston and Patricia Baysinger, vol. 14. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1983.Google Scholar
  15. Dietrich, Franz, and Luca Moretti. 2005. On coherent sets and the transmission of confirmation. Philosophy of Science 72:403–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Donagan, Alan. 1977. The theory of morality. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  17. Douven, Igor, and Wouter Meijs. 2007a. On the alleged impossibility of coherence. Synthese 157:347–360.Google Scholar
  18. Douven, Igor, and Wouter Meijs. 2007b. Measuring coherence. Synthese 156:405–425.Google Scholar
  19. Dyson, Freeman. 1988. Infinite in all directions. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  20. Edvardsson, Karin, and Sven Ove Hansson. 2005. When is a goal rational? Social Choice and Welfare 24:343–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Flanagan, Owen. 1986. Admirable immorality and admirable imperfection. The Journal of Philosophy 83:41–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Foot, Philippa. 1972. Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. Philosophical Review 81:305–316. In Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy, 157–173. Oxford: Basil Blackwell and Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978.Google Scholar
  23. Frankena, William K. 1973. Ethics. 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  24. Franklin, James. 2001. The science of conjecture: Evidence and probability before Pascal. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Gauthier, David. 1986. Morals by agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  26. Gert, Bernard. 1998. Morality: Its nature and justification. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Gert, Bernard. 2004. Common morality: Deciding what to do. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Hausman, Daniel M. 1991. Is utilitarianism useless? Theory and Decision 30:273–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Hempel, Carl G. 1965. Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: The Free Press and London: Collier-Macmillan.Google Scholar
  30. Hume, David. 1739. A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973.Google Scholar
  31. Irvine, William B. 2006. On desire: Why we want what we want. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Jeffrey, Richard C. 1992. Probability and the art of judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kuipers, Theo A. F. 2000. From instrumentalism to constructive realism. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Larmore, Charles. 2008. The autonomy of morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Laudan, Larry. 1984. Science and values: The aims of science and their role in scientific debate. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  36. Lehrer, Keith. 2000. Theory of knowledge. 2nd ed. Boulder: Westview.Google Scholar
  37. Lewis, C. I. 1946. An analysis of knowledge and valuation. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  38. Mackie, J. L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
  39. Maimonides, Moses. 1190. Dalālat al-ḥā’irīn. English edition: Maimonides, Moses. 1963. The guide of the perplexed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  40. Marx, Karl. 1939. Grundrisse der kritik der politischen ökonomie (Rohentwurf) 1857–1858. Moskau: Verlag für Fremdsprachige Literatur. English excerpts: Marx, Karl. 1977. Grundrisse. In Karl Marx: Selected Writings, ed. David McLellan, 345–387. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  41. McGee, Vann. 1985. A counterexample to modus ponens. The Journal of Philosophy 82:462–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Moretti, Luca. 2007. Ways in which coherence is confirmation conducive. Synthese 157:309–319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Morton, Adam. 1991. Disasters and dilemmas. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  44. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. 1979. The Belmont report. Office of Human Subjects Research. http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/humansubjects/guidance/belmont.html. Accessed 30 April 2014.
  45. Olsson, Erik J. 2005a. The impossibility of coherence. Erkenntnis 63:387–412.Google Scholar
  46. Olsson, Erik J. 2005b. Against coherence: Truth, probability, and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  47. Ortega y Gasset, José. 1936. History as a system. In Philosophy and history: Essays presented to Ernst Cassirer, eds. Raymond Klibansky and H. J. Paton, 283–322. Oxford: The Clarendon Press. In History as a system and other essays toward a philosophy of history, 165–233. New York: Norton, 1961.Google Scholar
  48. Pigozzi, Gabriella. 2009. Interview with John Woods. The Reasoner 3 (3): 1–4.Google Scholar
  49. Plato. Republic. In Complete works, ed. John M. Cooper, 971–1223. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1997.Google Scholar
  50. Polya, George. 1954. Mathematics and plausible reasoning. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Prichard, H. A. 1912. Does moral philosophy rest upon a mistake? In Moral obligation: Essays and lectures, 1–17. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949.Google Scholar
  52. Pryor, James. 2000. The skeptic and the dogmatist. Nous 34:517–549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Sayre-McCord, Geoffrey. 1985. Coherence and models for moral theorizing. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 66:170–190.Google Scholar
  55. Scheid, Don E. 1983. Kant’s retributivism. Ethics 93:262–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Schupbach, Jonah N. 2008. On the alleged impossibility of Bayesian coherentism. Philosophical Studies 141:323–331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Searle, John R. 1969. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Shogenji, Tomoji. 1999. Is coherence truth conducive? Analysis 59:338–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Shulman, Ken. 1993. AIDS without tears. Newsweek, Atlantic edition, August 23:60.Google Scholar
  60. Sidgwick, Henry. 1907. The methods of ethics. 7th ed. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  61. Simon, Herbert A. 1983. Reason in human affairs. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  62. Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 2006. Moral skepticisms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Sorensen, Roy A. 1990. Vagueness implies cognitivism. American Philosophical Quarterly 27:1–14.Google Scholar
  64. Welch, John R. 2014. Plausibilistic coherence. Synthese 191:2239–2253. doi:10.1007/s11229-013-0395-9.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Saint Louis University – Madrid CampusMadridSpain

Personalised recommendations