Skip to main content

The Hero, the Wolf, and the Hybrid: Overcoming the Overcoming of Uncultured Landscapes

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

In this chapter, Nathan Kowalsky reconnects the wolf as a symbol for the wild, with some of the themes that were developed earlier in this volume. Kowalsky criticizes the idea that cultural landscapes such as the rural landscapes of Europe are hybrids that step outside the binary thinking of humanity vs. nature, and thus offer grounds for a more cosmopolitan and cross-culturally relevant environmental ethic. To the contrary, he argues, the equation of cultural with agricultural landscapes reinforces the very dichotomy it proposes to dissolve. Kowalsky uses Prokofiev’s “Peter and the Wolf” to show that putatively cultural landscapes are defined by domestication of animals and opposition to undomesticated landscapes as inappropriate for human involvement. The bucolic peace of rural Europe where “humanity” and “nature” appear to co-operate in mutually beneficial harmony is, in fact, a result of the successful domination of the wild other in both extirpating the wolf and relegating wildlands to largely aristocratic estates. Kowalsky argues that domesticated rural or urban landscapes do not exhaust the meaning of human culture, and that recognizing hunting as a landscape culture forces post-dichotomous thinking to be more critical: some landscape cultures may be less dominating and/or more natural than others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Callicott’s second point follows McKibben (1988); cf. Callicott 2002, 301.

  2. 2.

    Drenthen notes here that his understanding of wilderness is developed in earlier writings (Drenthen 1999, 2005, 2007), but its implications for landscape hermeneutics and the illegibility of wild places (spaces?) were drawn out in more detail in an earlier version of this paper presented at the Sixth Annual Joint Environmental Philosophy Meeting, Allenspark, Colorado, USA, 17 June 2009.

  3. 3.

    “Savage” is an etymological derivative of silvaticus, or forest-dweller.

  4. 4.

    In English, a boor is not clever but a “rustic ill-mannered fellow”, a pejorative term derived from the more neutral Dutch word boer, for “farmer” (The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology, s.v. “boor”).

  5. 5.

    Technically ducks and most songbirds are omnivores, but because – like seeds and nuts – insects shed no blood, Prokofiev’s neat categorizations and contrasts present both birds as trophically benign in contradistinction to carnivores.

  6. 6.

    Prokofieff (1961). This book does not have page numbers, but I understand its English text to be a close translation of the Russian original.

  7. 7.

    “Of course, one could argue that the idea of these places somehow represent the not-yet-symbolised is itself another symbolised meaning, but whether that paradox will prove to be a killing objection is yet an open question” (Drenthen 2009a, 303).

  8. 8.

    Diamond (1997, 168) also notes that only fourteen of the world’s 148 “big terrestrial herbivorous mammals” are suitable for domestication.

  9. 9.

    And so, according to Adorno and Horkheimer (1997), Enlightenment seeks to overcome domination by dominating it, and thus never escaping (what it thinks is) the barbarity of nature.

  10. 10.

    Paraphrasing Dr. Samuel Johnson. See also, Felipe Fernández-Armesto (2007, 37) for more on the comparison between the effects of foraging and farming on the landscape.

  11. 11.

    This is not to say that some forms of gardening or agriculture are less out of step with the original recalcitrance of the land than are other forms of gardening or agriculture. Cf. Glenn Deliège’s contribution to this volume.

  12. 12.

    “[N]ot only does the wild serve no discernible advantage for the farmer and for agrarian societies in general, but it seems to actively hinder and undermine … the domestic human order” (Kover 2008, 240; cf. Shepard 1982, 23, 28, 35).

  13. 13.

    I owe this turn of phrase to T.R. Kover, who in turn derived it from Paul Shepard’s treatment of “the ethic of the barnyard.” See Kover (2012); Shepard (1999b, 60–61); and Shepard (1967, 190–205). To our knowledge, Shepard did not articulate his ethic of the barnyard as a metaphysic per se.

  14. 14.

    E.g., Varner (1995); Cowen (2003); Nussbaum and Faralli (2007); Raterman (2008); as opposed to Callicott (1980); Hettinger (1994); Kover (2010).

  15. 15.

    Shepard (1993, 289–290) also notes that these treaty relationships were always understood metaphorically, but that animal domestication collapsed the distinction between literal and figurative. I would suggest this as another reason why Social Darwinism can only arise within an agricultural context.

  16. 16.

    I offer one caveat here: there is a form of hunting which intentionally pursues “dangerous game”, such as grizzly bears, lions or Cape buffalo. Theodore Vitali (2010, 24) notes that “[i]n this model, the hunted animal is perceived as a threat to the hunter and thus the hunter-hunted relationship is viewed as mortal combat in which there is parity of danger: for one or the other, the outcome will be final.”

  17. 17.

    T.R. Kover, e-mail message to author, 6 December 2011.

  18. 18.

    ARK, “Death as Part of Nature,” http://www.arknature.eu/ark-en/nature-development/natural-processes/predation-and-death (accessed May 4, 2011).

  19. 19.

    “We see it as our duty in the debate to put the interests of the animals first: are these measures really benefiting the animals? Wild animals are really best off when there is least interference by humans. It is always the hunters who are asking for supplementary feed to be provided to prevent an agonizing demise” (Esther Ouwehand, Member of the Dutch Parliament, Party for Animal Rights). “It really is an ideal situation in the Oostvaardersplassen. Animals dying just happens to be a fact of life. Unfortunately, huntsmen have a really powerful lobby aimed at doing away with this natural system” (Pauline de Jong, Secretary of the Fauna Protection Society; cf. Kleis 2010).

  20. 20.

    I would like to thank Steven Vogel, Martin Drenthen, Thom Heyd, Allen Habib, Jozef Keulartz, Glenn Deliège and T.R. Kover for helpful criticisms of earlier drafts of this paper.

References

  • Adorno T.W., and M. Horkheimer. 1997. Dialectic of Enlightenment. Trans. John Cumming. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J.B. 1980. Animal liberation: A triangular affair. Environmental Ethics 2(4): 311–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J.B. 1992. La Nature est morte, vive la nature! Hastings Center Report 22(5): 16–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J.B. 2002. My reply. In Land, value, community: Callicott and environmental philosophy, ed. W. Ouderkirk and J. Hill, 291–329. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cowen, T. 2003. Policing nature. Environmental Ethics 25(2): 169–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Day, G.M. 1953. The Indian as an ecological factor in the northeastern forest. Ecology 34(2): 329–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, J. 1997. Guns, germs and steel: A short history of everybody for the last 13,000 years. London: Vintage/Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drenthen, M. 1999. The paradox of environmental ethics: Nietzsche’s view of nature and the wild. Environmental Ethics 21(2): 163–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drenthen, M. 2005. Wildness as a critical border concept: Nietzsche and the debate on wilderness restoration. Environmental Values 14(3): 317–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drenthen, M. 2007. New wilderness landscapes as moral criticism; a Nietzschean perspective on our fascination with wildness. Ethical Perspectives 14(4): 371–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drenthen, M. 2009a. Ecological restoration and place attachment: Emplacing non-places? Environmental Values 18(3): 285–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drenthen, M. 2009b. Fatal attraction: Wildness in contemporary film. Environmental Ethics 31(3): 297–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drenthen, M. 2011. Reading ourselves through the land: Landscape hermeneutics and ethics of place. In “Placing” nature on the borders of religion, philosophy & ethics, ed. F. Clingerman and M. Dixon, 123–138. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández-Armesto, F. 2007. The world: A history. Upper Saddle River: Pearson/Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A. 2001. Neo-Darwinian Leisures, the body and nature: Hunting and angling in modernity. Body & Society 7(4): 57–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freudenberger, D. 1987. Agriculture in a post-modern world. Paper presented at the conference toward a post-modern world, Santa Barbara, CA, January 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. 1991. Simians, cyborgs, and women: The reinvention of nature. London: Free Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, R.P. 1992. Forests: The shadow of civilization. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hettinger, N. 1994. Valuing predation in Rolston’s environmental ethics: Bambi lovers versus tree huggers. Environmental Ethics 16(1): 3–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kay, C.E. 1994. Aboriginal overkill: The role of Native Americans in structuring western ecosystems. Human Nature 5(4): 359–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellert, S.R. 1978. Attitudes and characteristics of hunters and antihunters. In Transactions of the forty-third North American wildlife and natural resources conference, 412–423. Washington, DC: Wildlife Management Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleis, R. 2010. Oostvaardersplassen, everyone HAPPY? Resource for Wageningen UR students and employees, Science, December 2010. http://resource.wageningenur.nl/en/show/Oostvaardersplassen-Everyone-HAPPY.htm. Accessed 7 Jan 2014.

  • Kover, T.R. 2008. The domestic order and its feral threat: Paul Shepard on the intellectual heritage of the neolithic landscape (unpublished draft).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kover, T.R. 2009. The domestic order and its feral threat: The intellectual heritage of the neolithic landscape. In Nature, space and the sacred: Transdisciplinary perspectives, ed. S. Bergmann et al., 235–245. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kover, T.R. 2010. Flesh, death, and tofu: Hunters, vegetarians, and carnal knowledge. In Hunting–philosophy for everyone: In search of the wild life, ed. N. Kowalsky, 171–183. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kover, T.R. 2012. The domestication of the human mind: Paul Shepard on the metaphysics of the barnyard. PhD dissertation, KULeuven.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.R. 1995. Native americans and the environment: A survey of twentieth-century issues. American Indian Quarterly 19(3): 423–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKibben, B. 1988. The end of nature. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, L. 1934. Technics and civilization. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadasdy, P. 2005. Transcending the debate over the ecological noble Indian: Indigenous peoples and environmentalism. Ethnohistory 52(2): 291–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, R. 1993. Understanding Eskimo science: Traditional hunters’ insights into the natural world are worth rediscovering. Audubon 95(5): 102–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C., and C. Faralli. 2007. On the new frontiers of justice: A dialogue. Ratio Juris 20(2): 157–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. 2000. Warranted Christian belief. Oxford: New York.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plumwood, V. 1998. Wilderness skepticism and wilderness dualism. In Great new wilderness debate, ed. J.B. Callicott and M.P. Nelson The, 652–690. Athens: University of Georgia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prokofieff, S. 1961. Peter and the wolf. New York: Franklin Watts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raterman, T. 2008. An environmentalist’s lament on predation. Environmental Ethics 30(4): 417–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolston III, H. 1988. Environmental ethics: Duties to and values in the natural world. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston III, H. 1992. Disvalues in nature. The Monist 75(2): 250–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolston III, H. 1994. Conserving natural value. New York: Columbia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanday, P.R. 1988. Divine hunger: Cannibalism as a cultural system. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, P. 1967. Man in the landscape: A historic view of the esthetics of nature. New York: P Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, P. 1982. Nature and madness. Athens: University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, P. 1992. A post-historic primitivism. In The wilderness condition: Essays on environment and civilization, ed. M. Oelschlaeger, 40–88. Washington, DC/Covelo: Island/Shearwater.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, P. 1993. On animal friends. In The biophilia hypothesis, ed. S.R. Kellert and E.O. Wilson, 275–300. Washington, DC/Covelo: Island/Shearwater.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, P. 1999a. Five green thoughts. In Encounters with nature: Essays by Paul Shepard, ed. F.R. Shepard, 117–133. Washington, DC/Covelo: Island/Shearwater.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, P. 1999b. Reverence for life at Lambaréné. In Encounters with nature: Essays by Paul Shepard, ed. F.R. Shepard, 56–66. Washington, DC/Covelo: Island/Shearwater.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spence, M.D. 1999. Dispossessing the wilderness: Indian removal and the making of the national parks. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tudge, C. 1998. Neanderthals, bandits and farmers: How agriculture really began. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varner, G. 1995. Can animal rights activists be environmentalists? In Environmental philosophy and environmental activism, ed. D.E. Marietta Jr. and L. Embree, 169–201. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vitali, T.R. 2010. But they can’t shoot back: What makes fair chase fair? In Hunting–philosophy for everyone: In search of the wild life, ed. N. Kowalsky, 23–31. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wawatie, J., and S. Pyne. 2010. Tracking in pursuit of knowledge: Teachings of an Algonquin Anishinabe bush hunter. In Hunting–philosophy for everyone: In search of the wild life, ed. N. Kowalsky, 93–105. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathan Kowalsky .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kowalsky, N. (2014). The Hero, the Wolf, and the Hybrid: Overcoming the Overcoming of Uncultured Landscapes. In: Drenthen, M., Keulartz, J. (eds) Old World and New World Perspectives in Environmental Philosophy. The International Library of Environmental, Agricultural and Food Ethics, vol 21. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-07683-6_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics