Skip to main content

Abstract

This conclusion summarizes the main theses of the book: (1) that Charron proposes an Academic skeptical view of wisdom; (2) that Gassendi’s revival of ancient skepticism was mainly inspired by Charron’s opposition to dogmatic science; (3) that La Mothe Le Vayer’s attack on superstition and strong attachment to opinions in general also was a development of Charron’s Academic skeptical wisdom; (4) that Descartes’s use of skepticism and doubt was crucially mediated by Charron’s and (5) that he, like Pascal, opposed Charron’s skeptical view of wisdom, though based on different grounds and for quite different purposes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See also the more recent and shorter survey by Casini (2009, 40–46) and Giocanti (2013).

  2. 2.

    Jardine (1983) shows that Academic skepticism was viewed by major Renaissance authors, in the footsteps of Cicero, as the epistemology compatible with rethorics. Granada (2001) examines the first reception of Academic skepticism in Italy. Naya (2008, 2009) has examined a variety of receptions of ancient Pyrrhonism and Academic skepticism in the Renaissance and argued that the latter—but not the former—was viewed by Christian authors, following Augustine, as capable of leading to Christian faith. This interpretation of Academic skepticism favored its reception at the time. Levy (2001) and Laursen (2009) have examined Pedro de Valencia’s reception of Academic skepticism. Panichi (2009) and earlier Limbrick (1972) and Eva (2013) have argued for the relevance of Academic skepticism in Montaigne’s kind of skepticism which has been almost exclusively related to ancient Pyrrhonism. Limbrick (1972) claims that Montaigne’s reception resembles Augustine whereas Panichi shows the great relevance of Plutarch’s middle Platonic view of Academic skepticism as characterized by the search for the truth.

  3. 3.

    Both Popkin (2003, 35) and Schmitt (1972, 165ff, 1983, 233) believed that because Sextus’ works were much more philosophically interesting than Cicero’s Academica, only after the former became available did skepticism became central in early modern philosophy. Popkin also believed that Sextus’ more sophisticated skepticism became very influential because it coincided with the problem, emerged in the Reform and the religious controversies it suscitated, of justifying religious knowledge claims. This generated what he called a “crise pyrrhonienne” in the sixteenth century. I quote the opening paragraph of the first chapter of Popkin’s History of Scpeticism: “One of the main avenues through which the sceptical views of antiquity entered late Renaissance thought was a central quarrel of the Reformation, the dispute over the proper standard of religious knowledge, or what was called ‘the rule of faith.’ This argument raised one of the classical problems of the Greek Pyrrhonists, the problem of the criterion of truth. With the rediscovery in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries of writings of the Greek Pyrrhonist Sextus Empiricus, the arguments and views of the Greek sceptics became part of the philosophical core of the religious struggles then taking place. The problem of finding a criterion of truth, first raised in theological disputes, was then later raised with regard to natural knowledge, leading to la crise pyrrhonienne of the early sixteenth century” (2003, 3). For the fortune of Sextus’ works from the Middle Ages to the Renaissance, see Floridi (2002). For criticism of Popkin’s theory, see Ayers (2004), Perler (2004) and Maclean (2006).

  4. 4.

    See Van Leeuwen (1963, 90–120), Shapiro (1983, 15–73), and Popkin (2003, 208–218).

  5. 5.

    One of Pascal’s fragments about Descartes is the following one: “Descartes. Il faut dire en gros: cela se fait par figure et mouvement. Car cela est vrai, mais de dire quelles et composer la machine, cela est ridicule. Car cela est inutile et incertain et pénible” (La 84). Locke is the philosopher who most extensively and famously exposed the limits of natural philosophy along these lines: if the pre mechanical philosophy is basically tautological or unverifiable by experience, the new mechanical view makes it plan that natural philosophy can be only probable.

  6. 6.

    Gassendi (1962) contains all the rounds of the fight.

  7. 7.

    The literature on this debate is immense. Lennon (1993) provides a detailed analysis of the main philosophical issues controversed, first in the direct confrontation and then in the followers of Descartes’s and Gassendi’s, in particular in the two major ones in the period, respectively, Malebranche and Locke.

  8. 8.

    Arnauld (1777, vol. X, 342) claims that Tubero’s (the pseudonym used by La Mothe Le Vayer in the Dialogues faits à l’imitatioin des anciens) épochè is contrary to Christian faith.

  9. 9.

    See Wetsel (1994, 66–77, 113–119, 1999), Maia Neto (1995, 37–64), and above all the detailed study by Giocanti (2001a).

  10. 10.

    For the view that Pascal completely rejected Descartes’s philosophy, see, among others, Bouchilloux (1995, 235–254). For an interpretation of Pascal as diverging from, but deeply influenced by Descartes, see Carraud (1992).

  11. 11.

    Another such transitional figure is Glanvill, see Introduction, note 17.

  12. 12.

    Charron’s direct influence on Foucher, Huet and Bayle, which I suppose little, still waits further inquiry. In the case of Bayle, the article “Charron” in the Dictionary seems relevant to at least some aspects of his own skepticism. On Bayle’s reception of Charron, see Paganini (1980, 92–96), Bianchi (1988, 141–175), and Adam (1991, 202–206). Huet knew well Charron’s work. In his marginalia of Pascal’s Pensées, he notes that Pascal’s wager is a reappraisal of one of the arguments in Charron’s Trois Vérités (see Maia Neto and Popkin 1995 and Orcibal 1956). Although the list of Huet’s personal library indicates Charron’s works, I could not find the books in the collection preserved in the Bibliothèque Nationale in Paris. In any event, Charron does not seem directly relevant to the main skeptical arguments in the Traité Philosophique. Finally, Foucher’s philosophy is pretty much the result of his engagement with Cartesianism. Charron’s Wisdom seems to play no role in it.

  13. 13.

    I argue in Maia Neto (1999) that Bayle’s skepticism is Academic and show his reception and modifications of the skepticisms exhibited by Charron, La Mothe Le Vayer, Descartes and Pascal.

  14. 14.

    See Huet (1974, chapter 6: “Quelle est la fin que l’on se propose dans l’art de douter”). Avoiding error is the immediate end, the ultimate end is to prepare for the reception of religious truth. For Huet’s fierce reaction to Descartes’s view of the plain truth, see Lennon (2008). For the presence of Descartes’s doubt in Huet’s skepticism, see Maia Neto (2008). For that of Pascal’s, see Maia Neto (2006).

  15. 15.

    For details of the project and the role of Carteasianism in it, see Watson (1966, 1987) and Maia Neto (2003).

  16. 16.

    See Maia Neto (1997) and Paganini (1984, 1991, 151–196, 2004, 2010).

  17. 17.

    See letters to Heinrich Köselitz from 30 March and 16 April 1881, in eKGWB/BVN, 1881, 97 and 103. I thank Rogério Lopes for calling my attention to these references.

Bibliography

  • Adam, Michel. 1991. Etudes sur Pierre Charron. Talence: Presses Universitaires de Bordeaux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnauld, Antoine. 1774. Œuvres, 38 vols. Lausenne: Sigismond. d’Arnay.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayers, Michael. 2004. Popkin’s revised scepticism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12: 319–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, Lorenzo. 1988. Tradizione liberina e critica storica. Milano: Franco Angeli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouchilloux, Hélène. 1995. Apologétique et raison dans les Pensées de Pascal. Paris: Klincksieck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carraud, Vincent. 1992. Pascal et la philosophie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casini, Lorenzo. 2009. Self-knowledge, scepticism and the quest for a new method: Juan Luis Vives on cognition and the impossibility of perfect knowledge. In Renaissance scepticisms, ed. G. Paganini and J.R. Maia Neto, 33–60. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eva, Luiz. 2013. Montaigne et les Academica de Cicéron. Astérion. Philosophie, histoire des idées, pensée politique 11. http://asterion.revues.org. Acessed 18 Aug 2013.

  • Floridi, Luciano. 2002. Sextus Empiricus. The transmission and recovery of Pyrrhonism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gassendi, Pierre. 1962. Disquisitio metaphysica seu dubitationes et instantiae adversus Renati Cartesii metaphysicam et responsa. Texte établie, traduit et annoté par B. Rochot. Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giocanti, Sylvia. 1996. La perte du sens commun dans l’oeuvre de La Mothe Le Vayer. Libertinage et philosophie au XVIIe siècle 1: 27–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giocanti, Sylvia. 2001a. Penser l’irrésolution. Montaigne, Pascal, La Mothe Le Vayer. Trois itinéraires sceptiques. Paris: Honoré Champion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giocanti, Sylvia. 2001b. La Mothe Le Vayer et la pratique du doute. La Lettre clandestine 10: 31–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giocanti, Sylvia (ed.). 2013. Dossier: La réception des Académiques dans l’age moderne. Astérion. Philosophie, histoire des idées, pensée politique 11. http://asterion.revues.org. Accessed 18 Aug 2013.

  • Granada, Miguel. 2001. Apologétique platonicienne et apologétique sceptique: Ficin, Savonarole, Jean-François Pic de la Mirandole. In Le scepticism au XVI e et au XVII e siècle, ed. P.-F. Moreau, 11–47. Paris: Albin Michel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huet, Pierre-Daniel. 1974. Traité philosophique de la foiblesse de l’esprit humain. Hildesheim: Olms.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine, Lisa. 1983. Lorenzo Valla: Academic skepticism and the new humanist dialectic. In The Skeptical tradition, ed. Myles Burnyeat, 253–286. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Labrousse, Elisabeth. 1964. Pierre Bayle, 2 vols. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laursen, John Christian. 2009. Pedro de Valencia’s Academica and scepticism in late Renaissance Spain. In Renaissance skepticisms, ed. G. Paganini and J.R. Maia Neto, 111–123. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennon, Thomas M. 1993. The Battle of the gods and giants: The legacies of Descartes and Gassendi. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennon, Thomas M. 2008. The plain truth. Descartes, Huet and skepticism. Leiden: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Carlos. 2001. Pierre de Valence, historien de l’Académie ou académicien? In Le scepticisme au XVI e et au XVII e sècle, ed. P.-F. Moreau, 174–187. Paris: Albin Michel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Limbrick, Elaine. 1972. Montaigne et Saint Augustin. Bibliothèque d’humanisme et renaissance 34: 49–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclean, Ian. 2006. The ‘Sceptical crisis’ reconsidered: Galen, rational medicine and the libertas philosophandi. Early Science and Medicine 11: 247–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maia Neto, José R. 1995. The Christianization of Pyrrhonism: Scepticism and faith in Pascal, Kierkegaard, and Shestov. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maia Neto, José R. 1997. Academic skepticism in early modern philosophy. Journal of the History of Ideas 58: 199–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maia Neto, José R. 1999. Bayle’s academic skepticism. In Everything connects: In conference with Richard H. Popkin, ed. James E. Force and David S. Katz, 263–276. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maia Neto, José R. 2003. Foucher’s academic Cartesianism. In Cartesian views. Papers presented to Richard A. Watson, ed. Thomas Lennon, 71–95. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maia Neto, José R. 2006. “As principais forças dos pirrônicos” (La 131) e sua apropriação por Huet. Kriterion: revista de filosofia 47: 237–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maia Neto, José R. 2008. Huet sceptique cartésien. Philosophiques 35: 223–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maia Neto, J. R., and Richard H. Popkin. 1995. Bishop Pierre-Daniel Huet’s remarks on Pascal. British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3: 147–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, Antony. 1990. De Pascal à Voltaire. Le rôle des Pensées de Pascal dans l’hisotire des idées entre 1670–1734, 2 vols. Oxford: The Voltaire Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naya, Emmanuel. 2008. Le ‘coup de Talon’ sur l’impiété: scepticisme et vérité chrétienne au XVIe siècle. Les Études philosophiques 2: 141–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naya, Emmanuel. 2009. Renaissance Pyrrhonism: A relative phenomenon. In Renaissance scepticisms, ed. G. Paganini and J. Maia Neto, 11–32. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2013. Digitale kritische gesamtausgabe werke und briefe (eKGWB). http://nietzschesource.org. Accessed 12 May 2013.

  • Orcibal, Jean. 1956. Le Fragment Infini-Rien et ses sources. In Blaise Pascal: l’homme et l’œuvre, 159–186. Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paganini, Gianni. 1980. Analise dela fede e critica dela ragione nella filosofia di Pierre Bayle. Firenze: La Nuova Italia Editrice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paganini, Gianni. 1984. Hume, il dubbio ‘pirroniano’ e la scepsi ‘accademica’. In La Storia dela filosofia come sapere critico. Studi offerti a Mario Dal Pra, 156–185. Milano: Franco Angeli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paganini, Gianni. 1991. Scepsi moderna. Interpretazioni dello scetticismo da Charron a Hume. Busento: Cosenza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paganini, Gianni. 2004. Hume, Bayle et les Dialogues concerning natural religion. In Pierre Bayle dans la république des lettres. Philosophie, religion, critique, ed. Antony McKenna and Gianni Paganini, 527–567. Paris: Honoré Champion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paganini, Gianni. 2008. Skepsis. Le débat des modernes sur le scepticisme. Montaigne – Le Vayer – Campanella – Hobbes – Descartes – Bayle. Paris: J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paganini, Gianni. 2010. Le scepticisme, une “maladie” ou un remède? Bayle, Crousaz, Hume. Libertinage et philosophie au XVIIe siècle 12: 191–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Panichi, Nicola. 2009. Montaigne and Plutarch: A scepticism that conquers the mind. In Renaissance skepticisms, ed. G. Paganini and J.R. Maia Neto, 183–211. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perler, Dominik. 2004. Was there a “Pyrrhonian Crisis” in early modern philosophy? A critical notice of Richard Popkin. Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie 86: 209–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pintard, René. 1983. Le Libertinage érudit dans la première moitiè du XVII e siècle.Nouvelle édition augmentée d’un avant-propos et de notes et réflexions sur les problèmes de l’histoire du libertinage. Genève/Paris: Slatkine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popkin, Richard H. 2003. The history of scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, Charles. 1972. Cicero scepticus. A Study of the influence of The Academica in the Renaissance. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, Charles. 1983. The rediscovery of ancient skepticism in modern times. In The Skeptical tradition, ed. Myles Burnyeat, 225–251. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Barbara. 1983. Probability and certainty in seventeenth-century England. A study of the relationships between natural science, religion, history, law, and literature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Leeuwen, Henry. 1963. The problem of certainty in English thought. 1630–1690. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Richard. 1966. The downfall of Cartesianism, 1673–1712. A study of epistemological issues in late seventeenth century Cartesianism. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Richard. 1987. The breakdown of Cartesian metaphysics. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wetsel, David. 1994. Pascal and disbelief. Catechesis and conversion in the Pensées. Washington: The Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wetsel, David. 1999. La Mothe Le Vayer and the subversion of Christian belief. Seventeenth-Century French Studies 21: 183–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Neto, J.R.M. (2014). Conclusion. In: Academic Skepticism in Seventeenth-Century French Philosophy. International Archives of the History of Ideas Archives internationales d'histoire des idées, vol 215. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-07359-0_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics