Skip to main content

Well-Being, Science, and Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Well-Being in Contemporary Society

Part of the book series: Happiness Studies Book Series ((HAPS))

Abstract

Academic research on well-being is pursued in multiple disciplines and currently exploding. Governments are also interested in the topic, as witnessed by their recent efforts to develop statistical measures of progress that include well-being indicators. Combined, this interest opens the door to the fruitful application of well-being research to society. Research on well-being, however, is not always well integrated across the disciplines that purport to study it. In particular, there is insufficient communication between the empirical study of well-being, and its normative/conceptual study as pursued in philosophy. This state of affairs is lamentable, as it robs science and public policy of the expertise of philosophers, a desirable tool when evaluating empirical claims about well-being promotion. In this article, I examine the reasons for this lack of communication. In particular, I reject the view according to which it originates in the idea that philosophers take well-being to be a single and general concept, and argue instead that it is likely to be the result of the different theoretical constraints under which philosophy and empirical science respectively operate. Finally, I show that communication can be strengthened by developing the empirical articulations of philosophical theories of well-being, and sketch how to do just that.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Notable examples are Alexandrova (2005, 2008, 2012a, b), Angner (2008, 2011, 2012), Feldman (2010), Haybron (2008), Sen (1985, 1987, 1992, 1993), Tiberius (2008), Tiberius and Plakias (2010). On the more purely empirical side of well-being research, scholars such as Diener, Frey, Kahneman, and Seligman have made consistent efforts at integrating work in psychology with economics and public policy (cf. Diener and Seligman (2004), Frey and Stutzer (2002), Kahneman (2000), Kahneman and Krueger (2006), Kesabir and Diener (2008), Stiglitz et al. (2010).

  2. 2.

    Note also that while I claim that these two types of questions are distinct, I also believe that they are in principle connected and should be answered by a unitary theory.

  3. 3.

    Though, what type of normativity, whether, that is, it is agent-relative or agent-neutral, has recently been disputed. See Darwall (2002) for a challenge to the default view that it is agent-relative rather than agent-neutral. See Rosati (2008) for a defence of the idea that well-being is agent-neutral as well as agent-relative.

  4. 4.

    Under this heading, we may regroup a number of theories that are, in fact, distinct in many ways. Some of them, for example, reduce the normative notion of well-being to the non-normative notion of rational desire understood conditionally as what an agent would desire, (a) on reflection; or (b) under idealized conditions; or (c) if she were fully informed; or again as (d) what a fully informed version of herself would want for herself as she actually is. Others, however, want to avoid this reduction and characterize well-being in terms that are themselves normative as what there is reason for an agent to desire. See Sidgwick (1907, 100–112), Brandt (1972, 686), Rawls (1972, 408), Railton (1986), Griffin (1986) and Skorupski (1999). I do not include in this class Desire Satisfactionism theories of well-being such as Heathwood (2011, 24–25) insofar as they explicitly deny that rational desires determine the prudential goodness of lives.

  5. 5.

    Hurka (1993), 3.

  6. 6.

    Sumner (1996), 24. Pace (McNaughton and Rawling 2001), 157–158; 158 n. 2.

  7. 7.

    I am assuming that there are cogent interpretations of Aristotle that do not make his theory straightforwardly perfectionist in the sense described above. Russell (2012, 44–64), for example, argues that Aristotle understands eudaimonia as an agent-relative good, and understands the virtues as benefiting their possessor in an agent-relative way.

  8. 8.

    What the latter consisted in is unfortunately a matter of exegetical dispute with important repercussions on the alleged objective nature of Aristotle’s view. According to most interpreters, the ergon at issue here makes a reference to Aristotelian ideas about the metaphysical/biological essence of human nature. According to another interpretation (Adkins 1984), however, the ergon at issue here is rather that which common practice in society assigns to each individual.

  9. 9.

    Sumner (1996, 156–171) actually claims that well-being is identical to authentic happiness. This is an important point within his theory, which, however, may harmlessly be ignored here.

  10. 10.

    Sumner (1996), pp 146–147.

  11. 11.

    This is true of all questions, except Question 32, which asks the patient to rate her overall quality of life compared with 10 years ago. If this question is asked before and after the intervention, this is of course another way of validating the impact of the intervention on the person’s current well-being.

  12. 12.

    Here too there are noticeable exceptions. See Railton (unpublished); Sumner (1996, Chap. 6); Tiberius and Plakias (2010).

  13. 13.

    Fore relevant references see footnote 4.

References

  • Adkins, A. W. H. (1984). The connection between Aristotle’s ethics and politics. Political Theory, 12, 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexandrova, A. Online first. Doing well in the circumstances. Journal of Moral Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexandrova, A. (2005). Subjective well-being and Kahneman’s objective happiness. Journal of Happiness Studies, 6(3), 301–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexandrova, A. (2008). First-person reports and the measurement of happiness. Philosophical Psychology, 21, 571–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexandrova, A. (2012a). Values and the science of well-being: A recipe for mixing. In the H. Kincaid (Eds.), Oxford handbook for philosophy of social science. https://docs.google.com/file/d/0B9W2e1dn9FOOVNnNktoaS1RU3M/edit?pli=1 Retrieved on February 8 2013

  • Alexandrova, A. (2012b). Well-being as an object of science. Philosophy of Science, 79, 5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angner, E. (2008). The philosophical foundations of subjective measures of well-being. In L. Bruni, F. Comim, & M. Pugno (Eds.), Capabilities and happiness (pp. 286–298). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angner, E. (2011). Are subjective measures of well-being ‘direct’? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(1), 115–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angner, E. (2012). Subjective well-being: When, and why it matters. (MS) Available at SSRN http://ssrn.com/abstract=2157140 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2157140

  • Argyle, M. (2001). The psychology of happiness. New York: Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1984). Nicomachean ethics. (W. D. Ross, Trans.). In J. Barnes(Eds.), The complete works of aristotle, 2 vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandt, R. (1972). Rationality, egoism, and morality. The Journal of Philosophy 69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruni, L., & Porta, P. L. (Eds.). (2005). Economics and happiness. Framing the Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruni, L., Comim, F., & Pugno, M. (Eds.). (2008). Capabilities and happiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2002). Welfare and rational care. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P. (2001). Human well-being and the natural environment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E. (1984). Subjective well-being. Psychological Bulletin, 95, 542–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., & Seligman, M. E. P. (2002). Very happy people. Psychological Science, 13(1), 81–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., & Seligman, M. E. P. (2004). Beyond money: Toward an economy of well-being. Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 5(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E., Sandvik, E., Pavot, W., & Fujita, F. (1992). Extraversion and subjective well-being in a U.S. national probability sample. Journal of Research in Personality, 26, 205–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin, R. A. (1974). Does economic growth improve the human lot? Some empirical evidence. In P. A. David & M. W. Reder (Eds.), Nations and households in economic growth: Essays in honour of Moses Abramowitz. New York and London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • European Commission. (2013). http://www.beyond-gdp.eu/ Accessed May 20 2013

  • Feldman, F. (2010). What is this thing called happiness?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, J. (1980). Natural law and natural rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S. (2008). Happiness: A revolution in economics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S., & Stutzer, A. (2002). Happiness and economics: How the economy and institutions affect well-being. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • German Council of Economic Experts & Conseil d’ Analyse Economique. (2010). Monitoring economic performance, quality of life and sustainability. http://www.sachverstaendigenrat-wirtschaft.de/fileadmin/dateiablage/Expertisen/2010/ex10_en.pdf Accessed May 20 2013

  • Griffin, J. (1986). Well-being: Its meaning, measurement and moral importance. Oxford: Oxford Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2008). The pursuit of unhappiness: The elusive psychology of well-being. Oxford: Oxford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood, C. (2011). Preferentism and self-sacrifice. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (1993). Perfectionism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • IOF (International Osteoporosis Foundation). (1997). Quality of life questionnaire: Qualeffo-41. http://www.iofbonehealth.org/sites/default/files/PDFs/Quality%20of%20Life%20Questionnaires/Qualeffo41_english_questionnaire.pdf

  • Italian National Council for Economics and Labour. (2013). First repot on equitable and sustainable well-being. http://www.misuredelbenessere.it/fileadmin/upload/Report_on_Equitable_and_Sustainable_Well-being_-_11_Mar_2013_-_Summary.pdf Accessed May 20 2013

  • Kahneman, D. (2000). Experienced utility and objective happiness: A moment based approach. In D. Kahneman & A. Tversky (Eds.), Choices, values, and frames. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Krueger, A. B. (2006). Developments in the measurement of subjective well-being. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 20(1), 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kesebir, P., & Diener, E. (2008). In defense of happiness: Why policymakers should care about subjective well-being. In L. Bruni, F. Comim & M. Pugno (Eds.), Capabilities and happiness (pp. 60–80). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, G. (1993). Aristotle and the ideal life. Philosophical Reivew, 102, 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layard, R. (2005). Happiness: Lessons from a new science. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lips, P., Cooper, C., Agnusdei, D. & et al. for the Working Party for Quality of Life of the European Foundation for Osteoporosis. (1999). Quality of life in patients with vertebral fractures: Validation of the quality of life questionnaire of the european foundation for osteoporosis (QUALEFFO). Osteoporos International, 10, 150–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lips, P., Cooper, C., Agnusdei, D., Caulin, F., Egger, P., Johnell, O., et al. (1997). Quality of life as outcome in the treatment of osteoporosis; the development of a questionnaire for quality of life by the European Foundation for Osteoporosis. Osteoporos International, 7, 36–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton, D., & Rawling, P. (2001). Achievement, welfare, and consequentialism. Analysis, 61, 2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • PubMed. (2013). http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/?term=well-being Accessed on May 25 2013

  • Railton, P. (1986). Facts and values. Philosophical Topics, 14, 2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1972). A theory of justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodogno, R. (2003). The role of well-being in ethics. Ph.D dissertation, University of St Andrews, St Andrews.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodogno, R. (2008). On the importance of well-being. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 11(2), 197–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, C. S. (2008). Objectivism and relational good. Social Philosophy and Policy, 25, 314–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. (2012). Happiness for humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M. (2011). Flourish: A visionary new understanding of happiness and well-being. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1985). Well-being, agency and freedom: The dewey lectures 1984. Journal of Philosophy, 82(4), 169–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1987). The standard of living. In A. Sen., J. Muellbauer, R. Kanbur, K. Hart, & B. Williams (Eds.), The standard of living: The tanner lectures on human values, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1992). Inequality re-examined. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1993). Capability and well-being. In M. Nussbaum., & A. Sen (Eds.), The quality of life, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 30–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1999). Development as freedom. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics (7th ed.). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skorupski, J. (1999). Ethical explorations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J. E., Sen, A., & Fitoussi, J.-P. (2010). Mismesuring our lives: Why GDP doesn’t add up. New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sumner, L. W. (1996). Welfare, happiness, and ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V. (2008). The reflective life: Living wisely with our limits. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tiberius, V., & Plakias, A. (2010). Well-Being. In J. M. Doris (Ed.), The moral psychology handbook. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Raffaele Rodogno .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rodogno, R. (2015). Well-Being, Science, and Philosophy. In: Søraker, J., Van der Rijt, JW., de Boer, J., Wong, PH., Brey, P. (eds) Well-Being in Contemporary Society. Happiness Studies Book Series. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-06459-8_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics