Skip to main content

Natural Mereology and Classical Mereology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Mereology and the Sciences

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 371))

Abstract

Two apparently opposing philosophical views on mereological issues are contrasted, and a device is suggesting for assessing the extent to which their difference is terminological, rather than substantial. According to the view associated with Classical Mereology, the part-whole relation is guaranteed, a priori, to have a particular and neat algebraic structure. According to a more naturalistic view, the global structure of the part-whole relation turns instead on how things in nature happen to be organized. The main technical idea of the paper is that there is a non-arbitrary way to transform any relation into one that obeys the axioms of Classical Mereology. The main philosophical idea is that if we apply the transformation to the ontology and structure the naturalistic philosopher believes in, the resulting Classical relational structure may be ontologically acceptable to the naturalistic philosopher, and the relation that relates the objects in the structure might be sufficiently “natural” that the naturalistic philosopher ought to acknowledge that it deserves the label “part-whole relation.” Thus, in the most dramatic case, the naturalistic philosopher might hold a view that turns out to be merely terminologically different from that of the Classical Mereologist. Sets, or pluralities, of the original naturalistic objects will typically be “added,” by the transformation, to the original ontology to which it is applied. This raises questions, only briefly addressed here, about the place of such entities in the study of part-whole relations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    If we reject a sharp distinction between a priori and not, in favor a graduated distinction, then we may substitute “very close to as a priori as it gets” for “a priori” here.

  2. 2.

    Lewis (1991, p. 75).

  3. 3.

    “Sparse,” because not every arbitrary collection corresponds to a universal.

  4. 4.

    See below for a formally exact statement of this constraint.

  5. 5.

    One can get an especially clear view of the effect of Φt by considering how it can be built up from iterated application of a simpler transformation. Define \(\varPhi _{t_{0}}\) so that

    $$\displaystyle{\varPhi _{t_{0}}(\langle X,\mathbf{R}\rangle ) =\langle X,\mathbf{R} \cup \{\langle x,z\rangle (\in X \times X): \exists y\,(x\mathbf{R}y \wedge y\mathbf{R}z)\}\rangle.}$$

    \(\varPhi _{t_{0}}(\mathfrak{B})\) is a first approximation of \(\varPhi _{t}(\mathfrak{B})\); a second approximation is \(\varPhi _{t_{0}}(\varPhi _{t_{0}}(\mathfrak{B}))\). One can show that \(\varPhi _{t}(\mathfrak{B})\) is the “limit” of the approximations. More precisely: let \(\mathfrak{B}^{0}\) be \(\mathfrak{B} =\langle X,\mathbf{R}\rangle\) and let \(\mathfrak{B}^{i+1}\) be \(\varPhi _{t_{0}}(\mathfrak{B}^{i})\). Let Ri be the relation in \(\mathfrak{B}^{i}\). Then Rt, the relation of \(\varPhi _{t}(\mathfrak{B})\), is the relation

    $$\displaystyle{\{\langle x,y\rangle (\in X \times X): \exists i \in \mathbb{N}\ \langle x,y\rangle \in \mathbf{R}^{i}\}.}$$
  6. 6.

    See Sect. 4 of Hovda (2009); the five conditions here correspond to the five axioms in the last of the five axiom-sets given there.

  7. 7.

    Given any structure \(\langle X,\mathbf{R}\rangle\), let \(A = \mathcal{P}(X)\). Given any x ∈ X, let \([x]\ =\ \{ y \in X: x\mathbf{R}y \wedge y\mathbf{R}x\}\). Let B be \(\{e \in A: \exists x \in X \wedge e = [x]\}\). Let S be the relation on B defined as follows: for any e and f in B,

    • eSf  if and only if  (∃z ∈ e)(∃w ∈ fzRw.

    Then define \(\varPhi _{a}(\langle X,\mathbf{R}\rangle ) =\langle B,\mathbf{S}\rangle\). In general, this transformation is much more natural when combined with prior application of Φr and Φt; the composite ΦaΦrΦt transforms any relational structure into a partial ordering.

  8. 8.

    For a fully general definition, we need some way to tell apart the members of a cluster that are of lower rank from the others; in our application, these were members of D rather than of E. Assuming that our set theory provides a natural way to rank everything in the universe (as does Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with ur-elements, choice, and foundation) a general transformation Φρ on arbitrary \(\langle X,\mathbf{R}\rangle\) may be defined by first applying Φt, then, taking a cluster to be a maximal set of members of X that bear Rt to one another, for each cluster, choosing its single lowest ranked member, if there is one, and the union of all its lowest-ranked sets, otherwise. Φρ is then defined by taking the “chosen” items as carrier set and taking the “inherited” relation.

  9. 9.

    A structure is a Complete Classical Mereology if it satisfies any standard set of axioms for Classical Mereology with the fusion axiom given set-theoretically. That is, the fusion axiom is a single axiom given with the use of set-theory, rather than an axiom scheme; see Sect. 1.2 of Hovda (2009).

  10. 10.

    See Hovda (2013) for a discussion of the interaction of formalistic mereology with time and tense. The main idea pursued in Hovda (2013) is to re-conceive formalistic mereology while taking tense (or metaphysical modality) seriously, and allowing objects (including fusions) to change their parts. To wed, in a natural way, the approach in Hovda (2013) with the idea in this paper would seem to require a set theory in which sets can change their members. Such a set theory should be buildable by modifying untensed set theory in something like the manner that Hovda (2013) modifies untensed Classical Mereology to yield a tensed mereology.

    Here is the barest sketch of how this would go. Naïve Set Theory consists of the axiom of Extensionality (sets x and y are the same iff x and y have the same members) together with the Naïve Comprehension scheme for set existence. The scheme is this (for any predicate ϕ(x) in which x occurs free and y does not, an instance of the scheme is): there exists at least one set y such that: for all x, x ∈ y iff ϕ(x). Let Tensed Naïve Set Theory be Tensed Extensionality (sets x and y are the same iff it is always the case that x and y have the same members) together with a tensed correlate of Comprehension: there exists at least one set y such that it is always the case that for all x (x ∈ y iff ϕ(x)). An instance of this scheme thus implies that there is a set y such that at every time, for every x, x ∈ y at that time iff x is (at that time) a dog. This set would have no members when there are no dogs, and its membership would wax and wane with the existence of dogs. Of course the tensed scheme inherits the inconsistency of the Naïve Comprehension scheme; to find a reasonable, consistent tensed set theory, one would modify ZFC with ur-elements, or the like.

References

  • Fine, K. (1999). Things and their parts. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23, 61–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2010). Towards a theory of part. Journal of Philosophy, 107(11), 559–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hovda, P. (2013). Tensed mereology. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42(2), 241–283. doi:10.1007/s10992-011-9220-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hovda, P. (2009). What is classical mereology? Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38(1), 55–82. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10992-008-9092-4.

  • Koslicki, K. (2008). The structure of objects. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophical, 61, 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1991). Parts of classes. Oxford/Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1990). Material beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Hovda .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hovda, P. (2014). Natural Mereology and Classical Mereology. In: Calosi, C., Graziani, P. (eds) Mereology and the Sciences. Synthese Library, vol 371. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05356-1_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics