Skip to main content

Building Enduring Objects Out of Spacetime

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Mereology and the Sciences

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 371))

Abstract

Endurantism, the view that material objects are wholly present at each moment of their careers, is under threat from supersubstantivalism, the view that material objects are identical to spacetime regions. I discuss three compromise positions. They are alike in that they all take material objects to be composed of spacetime points or regions without being identical to any such point or region. They differ in whether they permit multilocation and in whether they postulate mereologically coincident entities.

  1. 1.

    If one embraces coinciding entities and rejects Strong Supplementation, one can say that material objects lack temporal parts even though they coincide with temporally extended regions that have temporal parts. One can get this far while confining oneself to the perdurantist’s simple fundamental ideology – a two-place predicate for parthood simpliciter.

  2. 2.

    If one invokes a more exotic piece of fundamental ideology (a more-than-two-place predicate for a ‘location-relative’ parthood relation), and if one still embraces coinciding objects and rejects Strong Supplementation, then one can say that material objects both lack temporal parts, in the manner of ‘mereological endurantism’, and are multilocated in spacetime, in the manner of ‘locational endurantism’. However, nearly all B-theoretic endurantists already help themselves to a fundamental relativized parthood predicate, even in the context of dualist substantivalism.

  3. 3.

    If one is willing to eliminate complex spacetime regions (in favor of sets or pluralities of points) and treat the fundamental parthood predicate as being both location-relative and non-distributive, one can reject temporal parts, retain locational endurantism, and avoid coinciding entities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The standard definition of ‘instantaneous temporal part’ runs as follows: ‘x is an instantaneous temporal part of y at t’ means ‘(i) t is an instant, (ii) x is a part of y at t, (iii) x overlaps-at-t every part-at-t of y, (iii) x is present at t, and (iv) x is not present at any other instant’. (This is based on Sider 2001, 59.) For other definitions, see Gibson and Pooley (2006, 163), Parsons (2007), and Balashov (2010, 73). The key point is that, in order for a thing y to count as a temporal part of a thing x, y must be a part of x and y must be spatially co-located with x at any moment at which y is present.

  2. 2.

    A-theories of time all say that there is a time that is present in some absolute, not-merely-indexical sense. That is, they say that there is a ‘metaphysically privileged’ present time. The B-theory of time denies this. Presentism is an A-theory of time according to which there are no non-present entities (such as, presumably, pre-Socratic philosophers and Martian outposts). Eternalism is the view that the past, present, and future all exist equally. See Sider (2001) and Markosian (2010) for more on these views.

  3. 3.

    See Haslanger (2003) for an overview of these issues.

  4. 4.

    See Hawthorne and Sider (2006) for a sophisticated discussion of this issue.

  5. 5.

    They can’t identify an object with its location in space, since objects often occupy different regions of space at different times, but no region of space occupies different regions at different times. And of course they can’t identify an object with its location in time – say, the interval that is the object’s total timespan. There are many reasons for this, but one of them is that, again, an object typically occupies different regions of space at different times, but no interval of time does this. Finally, they can’t identify a material object with a spacetime region, since they either reject spacetime regions altogether or treat them as set-theoretic constructs; and presumably material objects are not set-theoretic constructs. The shift from space and time to spacetime solves these problems. No region of space is in different places at different times, but there are regions of spacetime that are. And spacetime substantivalists are free to deny that spacetime regions are set-theoretic constructs.

  6. 6.

    As I will understand it, supersubstantivalism is neutral as to which regions count as material objects. (Every region? Every ‘matter-filled’ region? Every maximal continuous matter-filled region?) And then there is the further question of what counts as being ‘matter-filled’. Presumably this will need to be spelled out in field-theoretic terms, but even so the answer is hardly straightforward. Again, supersubstantivalists are free to disagree amongst themselves on these questions. They are united only in claiming that all material objects are regions.

  7. 7.

    Here are four such views. (i) Extended Simple Regions. Spacetime might be composed of spatially and temporally extended but mereologically simple ‘grains’. (See Braddon-Mitchell and Miller (2006) and Dainton (2010) for discussion of related views.) Such a grain might count as persisting (since it’s temporally extended), but it wouldn’t have any proper temporal parts, and so might not count as perduring. (ii) Spatially Gunky Spacetime. Spacetime might be ‘spatially gunky’ and altogether lacking in proper temporal parts: suppose that every spacetime region is complex, spatially extended, and of infinite temporal extent in both temporal directions, so that each region is eternal and composed of spatially smaller regions. These regions would count as persisting but not as perduring (and even opponents of extended simples can believe in them). (iii) Restricted Composition on Spacetime Points. Suppose that all spacetime regions are composed of spatially-and-temporally-unextended, mereologically simple spacetime points, and that some spacetime points compose something iff they are arranged ‘complete path of a living organism’-wise. Then, since no living organism has a spacetime point or another living organism as a proper temporal part (let’s assume), it’s plausible that no temporally extended region has any proper temporal parts. (The pluralities of simples that would compose the temporal parts of such regions, if they composed anything, do not in fact compose anything.) In that case there could be regions that persist but do not perdure. (iv) Mereologically Coinciding Regions Without Strong Supplementation. Suppose that all spacetime regions are composed of spatially-and-temporally-unextended simple spacetime points and that every plurality of points composes a region. But suppose further that there is at least one plurality of points, the ps, that compose two different regions, r1 and r2, such that: (a) r1 and r2 are both spatially and temporally extended, (b) r1 has a full distribution of proper temporal parts, and (c) r2 does not have any proper temporal parts. Thus the relationship between r1 and r2 is like the relationship between a statue and a lump that are composed of the same simples but that differ in that the head of the statue is a part of the statue but not of the lump. (Strong Supplementation – the principle that if x is not a part of y, then x has some part that fails to overlap y – is violated in such cases.) In such a case r2 would persist but not perdure. (Eagle (2010) floats a view that sanctions mereologically coincident spacetime regions but does not suggest that they might different with respect to having temporal parts.)

  8. 8.

    Hawthorne (2006) and Schaffer both seem to think that the constitution version is friendlier to certain forms of endurantism than is the identity version, although neither goes into much detail on this point. Hawthorne focuses mostly on forms of endurantism (framed in terms of grounding or metaphysical dependence) that will not concern us here. Schaffer’s reason for taking the constitution-version to be endurance-friendly is not clear to me. He writes that ‘the constitution view …does not entail four-dimensionalism …. Presumably the constituted object could have different persistence conditions than its constituting matter [a spacetime region]’ (Schaffer, 2009, 137).

  9. 9.

    Henceforth points (if there are any) count as regions.

  10. 10.

    This view would fail if (i) some sets of regions had no fusion at all, in which case a form of restricted composition would be true or (ii) some set of regions had more than one spacetime region as a fusion, as discussed in note 7.

  11. 11.

    To see this, note first that, given PCV together with our set-up, no region occupied by m is a part of any region occupied by Obama. But then, by Parts of Objects, we get the result that m is not a part of Obama. So the fundamental parthood relation expressed by ‘is a part of’ doesn’t hold between m and Obama. And according to Absolutism, this is the only fundamental parthood relation.

  12. 12.

    Many have argued that the fundamental parthood relation for material objects is a three-place relation expressed by ‘x is a part of y at z’, with two slots for material objects and one slot for a time (Thomson, 1983; Van Inwagen, 1990; Koslicki, 2008) or a region of space or spacetime (Rea, 1998; Hudson, 2001; McDaniel, 2004; Donnelly, 2010). As far as I am aware, the only self-described B-theoretic endurantist who accepts Absolutism is Parsons (2000, 2007).

  13. 13.

    Kleinschmidt (2011) independently proposes 4P and some of the same 4P-appropriate mereological principles to be given here. But she eventually rejects 4P.

  14. 14.

    B-theoretic endurantists who are on record in opposition to mereological coincidence without identity include Van Inwagen (1990), Burke (1994), Olson (1997), Rea (1998, 2000), Hershenov (2005), McGrath (2007), and Koslicki (2008). The argument for locational endurantism given in Gilmore (2007) depends upon the impossibility of mereological coincidence without identity.

  15. 15.

    See Linnebo (2012) on ‘is one of’ and plural quantification. My notation follows his.

  16. 16.

    Similarly, the dominant-kinds view developed in a dualist-substantivalist context by Burke (1994) and Rea (2000) can be developed in monist-substantivalist context with an appropriate replacement for ‘R’ in (i). Likewise for virtually any uniqueness-friendly endurantist theory of persistence-and-composition. See Markosian (2008) for more on restricted composition.

  17. 17.

    And if spacetime is composed of spatially extended simple ‘grains’, the existence of ‘spatially-grain-like’ material objects would be equally problematic for all three compromise positions, for parallel reasons.

  18. 18.

    We will assume that (i) x and y mereologically coincide, (ii) z is simple, and (iii) z is a part of x; we will show that z is a part of y, too. By (i) and the definition of ‘mereologically coincide’, it follows that (v) x and y overlap exactly the same things. By the reflexivity of parthood, (vi) z is a part of itself. Together with (iii) and the definition of ‘overlaps’, this entails that (vii) x overlaps z. Together with (v), this entails that y overlaps z. So, by the definition of ‘overlap’, (viii) there is a thing, call it w, that is a part of z and a part of y. But by the definition of ‘simple’, the only part of z is z itself. So w=z, and hence z is a part of y.

References

  • Balashov, Y. (2010). Persistence and spacetime. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2004). Spatiotemporal coincidence and the grounding problem. Philosophical Studies, 118(3), 339–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Miller, K. (2006). The physics of extended simples. Analysis, 66, 222–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burke, M. (1994). Preserving the principle of one object to a place: a novel account of the relations among objects, sorts, sortals and persistence conditions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, 591–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. (2010) Time and space (2nd ed.). Montreal: McGill-Queen’s.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, M. (2010). Parthood and multi-location. In D. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 5, pp. 203–243).

    Google Scholar 

  • Eagle, A. (2010). Perdurance and location. In D. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 5, pp. 53–94). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1989). World enough and spacetime. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, I. & Pooley, O. (2006). Relativistic persistence. In J. Hawthorne (Ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, 20, 157–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilmore, C. (forthcoming). Quasi-supplementation, plenitudinous coincidentalism, and gunk. In R. Garcia (Ed.), Substance: New essays. Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilmore, C. (2006). Where in the relativistic world are we? In J. Hawthorne (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives: metaphysics (Vol. 20, pp. 199–236). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilmore, C. (2007). Time travel, coinciding objects, and persistence. In D. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 3, pp. 177–198). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilmore, C. (2008). Persistence and location in relativistic spacetime. Philosophy Compass, 3/6, 1224–1254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilmore, C. (2009). Why parthood might be a four place relation, and how it behaves if it is. In L. Honnefelder, E. Runggaldier, & B. Schick (Eds.), Unity and time in metaphysics (pp. 83–133). Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2003). Persistence through time. In M. J. Loux & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics, (pp. 315–354). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2006). Metaphysical essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J., & Sider, T. (2006). Locations. In J. Hawthorne (Ed.), Metaphysical essays, (pp. 85–109). Ithaca: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hershenov, D. (2005). Do dead bodies pose a problem for biological approaches to personal identity? Mind, 114, 31–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, H. (2001). A materialist metaphysics of the human person. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, H. (2005) The metaphysics of hyperspace. Oxford: Oxford Univerty Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kleinschmidt, S. (2011). Multilocation and mereology. Philosophical Perspectives, 25(1), 253–276. J. Hawthorne (Ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2008). The structure of objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, Ø. (2012). Plural quantification. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2013 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/plural-quant/

  • Lowe, E. J. (2003). Substantial change and spatiotemporal coincidence. Ratio, 16, 140–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. (2008). Restricted composition. In T. Sider, J. Hawthorne, & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics, (pp. 341–363). London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. (2010). Time. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 ed.). http://pluto.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/time/

  • McDaniel, K. (2004). Modal realism with overlap. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82, 137–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2007). Four-dimensionalism and the puzzles of coincidence. In D. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 3, pp. 143–176). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2001). Objects and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. (1997). The human animal: Personal identity without psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, J. (2000). Must a four-dimensionalist believe in temporal parts? The Monist, 83, 399–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, J. (2007). Theories of location. In D. W. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics, (Vol. 3, pp. 201–232). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. (1998). In defense of mereological universalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(2), 347–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. (2000). Constitution and kind membership. Philosophical Studies, 97, 169–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). Spacetime the one substance. Philosophical Studies, 145, 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1983). Parthood and identity over time. Journal of Philosophy, 80, 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1990). Material beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cody Gilmore .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gilmore, C. (2014). Building Enduring Objects Out of Spacetime. In: Calosi, C., Graziani, P. (eds) Mereology and the Sciences. Synthese Library, vol 371. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05356-1_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics