Skip to main content

Conclusion

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Reforming the Art of Living

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies in Contemporary Culture ((PSCC,volume 24))

  • 487 Accesses

Abstract

To the extent that my argument in the preceding chapters has been successful, I have accomplished two goals. First, I have elucidated the nature of Descartes’s account of virtuous belief formation. Second, I have clarified the pragmatic and social nature of Descartes’s philosophical program, by showing how his account of virtuous belief formation is subversive of traditional Christianity and, by implication, of those traditional forms of religion with similar philosophical commitments. In this chapter, I conclude by summarizing my case and by describing in a bit more detail the significance of Descartes’s program.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Lest there be any misunderstanding, I am merely claiming that the kind of distinction on which Descartes relies is similar to that which Locke makes in his Essay. I am not claiming that there is a particular historic or causal connection between the two.

  2. 2.

    In this section, I am merely sketching the significance of Descartes’s project as it relates to those who followed him. A number of Orthodox Christian philosophers and theologians contend, however, that this kind of religious rationalism may have begun to take effect much earlier in the Latin-speaking West—see, e.g., Bradshaw (2004), Engelhardt (2000), Popovich (1994), and Romanides (2008) as well as Bradshaw (2006) and Lossky (1976; 2001).

  3. 3.

    See, e.g., the evidence that Descartes is sincere in his religious convictions in Chap. 7, Sect. 7.2.3.

  4. 4.

    Or of rationalism’s fideistic alter ego.

  5. 5.

    I have not attempted to address this issue. Rather, I attempted merely to explain some of the most significant ways that Descartes’s philosophical project both differs from and presents itself as an alternative to traditional Christianity—and, by implication, to those traditional forms of religion with similar philosophical commitments.

References

  • Bradshaw, D. 2004. Aristotle east and west: Metaphysics and the division of Christendom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bradshaw, D. 2006. The divine glory and the divine energies. Faith and Philosophy 23: 279–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, Rene. 1964–1976. Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. C. Adam and P. Tannery. Paris: Libraire Philosophique J. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, Rene. 1984–1985. The philosophical writings of Descartes. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, and Dugald Murdoch, vols. 1 and 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, Rene. 1991. The philosophical writings of Descartes. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny, vol. 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelhardt, H.T. 2000. The foundations of Christian bioethics. Lisse: Swets and Zeitlinger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, D. 2001. Descartes embodied: Reading Cartesian philosophy through Cartesian science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1960 [1793]. Religion within the limits of reason alone. Trans. T.M. Green and H.H. Hudson. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, A.D. 1993. Berkeley’s divine language argument. In George Berkeley, Alciphron, or the minute philosopher: In focus, ed. D. Berman, 185–199. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. 1975. An essay concerning human understanding, ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lossky, V. 1976. The mystical theology of the Eastern church. Crestwood: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lossky, V. 2001. The image and likeness of God, ed. J.H. Erickson and T.E. Bird. Crestwood: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossner, E.C. 2006 [1967]. Deism. In Encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Donald Borchert, vol. 2, 2nd ed, 680–693. New York: Thomson-Gale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popovich, J. 1994. Orthodox faith and life in Christ. Belmont: Institute for Modern Greek Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romanides, J. S. 2008. Patristic Theology. Trans. H. Alexios (Trader). Thessaloniki: Uncut Mountain Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. 1989 [1670]. Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, ed. and trans. S. Shirley. Leiden: Brill, anonymous.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toland, J. 1702. Christianity not mysterious: Or a treatise shewing, that there is nothing in the Gospel contrary to reason, nor above it: And that no Christian doctrine can be properly call’d a mystery. London, 1702.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Vitz, R. (2015). Conclusion. In: Reforming the Art of Living. Philosophical Studies in Contemporary Culture, vol 24. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05281-6_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics