Skip to main content

Mere Belief as a Modification

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Mind, Values, and Metaphysics
  • 594 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter uses the method of linguistic phenomenology to explain how belief in the sense of mere opinion can be understood as botched knowing. The distinction between attributive and nonattributive terms plays a central role in this explanation of belief. Several kinds of nonattributive terms are distinguished, modifying, restrictive and restorative terms, each being of use in the explanation of epistemic notions. And several forms of modification are distinguished: semantic, conceptual and ontological modification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The term ‘judgement’ itself may stand for the act of judgement, the judgement product, the judgement candidate or the faculty of judgement; cf. van der Schaar (2007).

  2. 2.

    These different meanings of the term ‘belief’ are given an account of in van der Schaar (2009). Unquestioned faith is perhaps not a case of belief that, but of belief in. Propositional truth and falsity do not seem to be applicable to the content of unquestioned faith.

  3. 3.

    ‘[P]ositive and negative conviction are ranged alongside each other on an equal footing’ Reinach (1911, p. 333). The original has: ‘Positive und negative Überzeugung stehen,…, einander gleichgeordnet gegenüber Cf. Mulligan (1987).’

  4. 4.

    The Dutch language has two question-words related to the two meanings of ‘cause’: (1) cause as reason, which may be asked for by a ‘waarom’ question, the ‘Why’ question mentioned above (‘Waarom geloof je dat?’); and (2) a metaphysical cause, which has the notion of effect as a counterpart. A cause in this sense may be asked for by a ‘waardoor’ question (‘Waardoor heb je die overtuiging?’, ‘What is the cause of your conviction?’).

  5. 5.

    ‘A thing becomes intelligible first when it is analysed into its constituent concepts.’ Moore (1899, p. 182).

  6. 6.

    In the paper I argue against Barbara Partee’s (2010) thesis that fake guns are a special case of guns, which means that on her account modifying or privative terms behave rather like relative terms.

  7. 7.

    I prefer this terminology to the less apt ‘redundant terms’: these terms are not redundant at all when used in the right context.

  8. 8.

    Markus Stepanians and Arianna Betti have already pointed to the Bolzano side of the topic, cf. Stepanians (1998, p. 28) and Betti (2006, p. 59).

  9. 9.

    Twardowski (1894, § 4, p. 12 ff.) uses the distinction between the modifying and the attributive sense of the term ‘presented’ to explain the distinction between the content and the object of an act. There is a distinction between presented object as object, where ‘presented’ is used in its attributive sense, because we say about the object that we have a presentation of it, and presented object as content, where ‘presented’ is taken in its modifying sense, because the term modifies the meaning of the term ‘object’. If ‘painted’ is used as modifying term in ‘painted landscape’, the landscape is a painted one, that is, not a true landscape (‘sie ist keine wahrhafte Landschaft,’ Twardowski 1894, p. 13). ‘Painted’ can also be used attributively: We can talk of a landscape near Amsterdam that was painted by Rembrandt.

  10. 10.

    Weidemann translates the example as follows: ‘Von etwas Nichtseiendem kann aber nicht deshalb, weil es ein vermeintliches (Seiendes) ist, wahrheitsgemäss ausgesagt werden, es sei ein Seiendes. Denn die (blosse) Meinung, (es sei), hat man von ihm ja nicht etwa deshalb, weil es (seiend) wäre, sondern gerade deshalb, weil es nicht(seiend) ist.’ Weidemann (1994, p. 24, 25).

  11. 11.

    Pascal Engel, Truth, Acumen, 2002, p. 128.

  12. 12.

    Cf. van der Schaar (2011a) and Adler (2002, p. 275): ‘From the first-person point of view, one treats one’s belief as factive, which is the central property of knowledge.’

  13. 13.

    I have given a full account of assertion in van der Schaar (2011b).

  14. 14.

    ‘Bloss (die Blösse) weist hier, wie überhaupt, auf einen Mangel hin; aber nicht immer ist ein Mangel durch eine Ergänzung zu beheben. So setzen wir ja der Wahrnehmung die “blosse” Einbildung gegenüber. Das Unterscheidende liegt in einem Vorzug auf Seiten der Wahrnehmung, aber nicht in einem Plus.’ Husserl (1901, V, § 28, p. 463).

  15. 15.

    ‘[D]ass blosses Urteilen eine intentionale Modifikation von erkennendem Urteilen ist.’ (Husserl 1939, § 5, p. 15). Stepanians (1998, Chap. 10) gives an extensive account of Husserl’s idea of modification in the fourth and fifth Logical Investigation.

  16. 16.

    As Augustine (1988) writes in the Confessiones, III. vii. 12: ‘I did not know [at that time] that evil was only the privation of good’.

  17. 17.

    ‘[W]hen we consider God’s decree and God’s nature, we can no more assert of that man that he is deprived of sight than we can assert it of a stone … privation is simply to deny of a thing something that we judge pertains to its nature,’ Ep. 21 to Willem van Blyenbergh (Spinoza 1992). In the Cogitata Metaphysica (1982, Part II, Chap. 7), Spinoza says that evil and sin are nothing in things, but only in the human mind as it compares things with one another.

References

  • Adler JE (2002) Belief’s own ethics. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1980) The metaphysics, vol I, II. Harvard University, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine (1988) Confessiones/Belijdenissen. Ambo, Baarn

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin JL (1946) Other minds. In: Austin JL (1970) Philosophical papers, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 76–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin JL (1956) A plea for excuses. In: Austin JL (1970) Philosophical papers, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 175–204

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin JL (1962) How to do things with words. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1984

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin JL (1964) Sense and Sensibilia. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Betti A (2006) The strange case of Savonarola and the painted fish; on the bolzanization of Polish thought. In: Chrudzimski A, Lukasiwicz D (eds) Actions, products and things. Ontos, Frankfurt, pp 55–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolzano B (1837/1929) Wissenschaftslehre. Felix Meiner, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano F (1870/2011) Logik. EL 80, In: Rollinger R. (ed) Salzburg. Available with: http://gandalf.uib.no/Brentano/texts/el/logik/norm/. Accessed 5 May 2013

  • Brentano F (1874/1925) Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, II. Felix Meiner, Hamburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano F (1914/1968) Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, III. Felix Meiner, Hamburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege G (1879/1971) Begriffsschrift. In: Angelelli I (ed) Begriffsschrift und andere Aufsätze. Georg Olms, Hildesheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker PMS (2004) Of the ontology of belief. In: Siebel M, Textor M (eds) Semantik und Ontologie. Ontos, Frankfurt, pp 185–222

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlyn DW (1993) Aristotle De Anima books II and III. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1739/2009) A treatise of human nature, vol I. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1748/1999) An enquiry concerning human understanding. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1901/2009) Logische Untersuchungen. Felix Meiner Verlag, Hamburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1939/1985) Erfahrung und Urteil. Felix Meiner Verlag, Hamburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Marty A (1884) Über subjektlose Sätze und das Verhältnis der Grammatik zu Logik und Psychologie, I. In: Marty A (1918) Gesammelte Schriften. Niemeyer, Halle, pp 3–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1843) A System of Logic. In: Robson JM (ed) (1973/1974) Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, vol 7, 8. University of Toronto, Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore GE (1899) The nature of judgment. Mind 8:176–193

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan K (1987) Promisings and other social acts: their constituents and structure. In: Mulligan K (ed) Speech Act and Sachverhalt; Reinach and the Foundations of Realist Phenomenology. Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht, pp 29–90

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan K (2013) Acceptance, acknowledgment, affirmation, agreement, assertion, belief, certainty, conviction, denial, judgment, refusal & rejection. In: Textor M (ed) Judgement and truth in early analytic philosophy and phenomenology. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, pp 97–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee B (2010) Privative adjectives: subsective plus coercion. In: Bauerle R, Reyle U, Zimmerman TE (eds) Presuppositions and discourse: essays offered to Hans Kamp. Emerald, Bradford, pp 273–285

    Google Scholar 

  • Price HH (1969) Belief. Allen & Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach A (1911) On the theory of the negative judgement. In: Smith B (ed) (1982) Parts and moments. Philosophia Verlag, München/Wien, pp 315–400

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza B (1982) Cogitata Metaphysica/Metafysische Gedachten, Appendix to Spinoza’s Descartes’ principles of philosophy. In: Spinoza B Korte Geschriften. Wereldbibliotheek, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza B (1992) Correspondence/Briefwisseling. Wereldbibliotheek, Amsterdam. English edition: Spinoza B (1995) The Letters (trans: Samuel S). Hackett, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Stepanians MS (1998) Frege und Husserl über Urteilen und Denken. Ferdinand Schöningh, Paderborn

    Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski K (1894) Zur Lehre vom Inhalt und Gegenstand der Vorstellungen Eine psychologische Untersuchung. Hölder, Wien. Second edition (1982) Philosophia Verlag, München, Wien

    Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski K (1912) Actions and products. Some remarks from the borderline of psychology, grammar and logic. In: Twardowski (1999) 103–132

    Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski K (1923) On the logic of adjectives in. Twardowski (1999), pp 141–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski K (1999) Brandl J, Woleński J (eds) On actions, products and other topics in philosophy. Rodopi, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Schaar M (2007) The assertion-candidate and the meaning of mood. Synthese 159:61–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van der Schaar M (2008) Locke and Arnauld on judgement and proposition. Hist Philos Logic 29:327–341

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van der Schaar M (2009) Judgement, belief and acceptance. In: Primiero G, Rahman S (eds) Acts of knowledge: history, philosophy and logic; essays dedicated to Göran Sundholm. College Publications, London, pp 267–286

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Schaar M (2011a) The cognitive act and the first-person perspective; an epistemology for constructive type theory. Synthese 180:391–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van der Schaar M (2011b) Assertion and grounding; a theory of assertion for constructive type theory. Synthese 183:187–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van der Schaar M (2014) Wooden horses and false friends; on the logic of adjectives. In: Mulligan K, Kijania-Placek K, Placek T (eds) The history and philosophy of polish logic; essays in honour of Jan Wolenski. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, 103–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Weidemann H (1994) Aristoteles, Peri Hermeneias. Akademia Verlag, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2000) Knowledge and its limits. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1951) Über Gewissheit. In: Wittgenstein L (1984) Werkausgabe 8. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a. M.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maria van der Schaar .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van der Schaar, M. (2014). Mere Belief as a Modification. In: Reboul, A. (eds) Mind, Values, and Metaphysics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05146-8_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics