Skip to main content

Embedding Illocutionary Acts

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Recursion: Complexity in Cognition

Part of the book series: Studies in Theoretical Psycholinguistics ((SITP,volume 43))

Abstract

Speech acts have sometimes been considered as not embeddable, for principled reasons. In this paper, I argue that illocutionary acts can be embedded under certain circumstances. I provide for a semantic interpretation of illocutionary acts as functions from world/time indices to world/time indices, which provides them with a semantic type, and allows for operators that take them as arguments. I will illustrate this with three cases: First, with illocutionary acts as arguments of verbs like tell, second, as semantic objects modified by speech act adverbials like frankly and third, with Austinian conditionals. By these exemplary cases, I show that illocutionary acts (or rather, speech-act potentials) become part of the recursive structure of language.

This paper had a long gestation period. It is part of ongoing work on the nature of speech acts and the interaction of It profited tremendously from comments of audiences on presentations of related material at Stanford University, University of California at Santa Cruz, the World Congress of Linguists in Seoul, the recursion conference in Amherst in 2009, the conference on sentence types and illocutionary acts at ZAS Berlin in 2010, and a talk at New York University, April 2013. The current paper focuses in particular on the issue of recursion of speech acts within the more general topic. There are too many colleagues that, in one way or other, had influence on the points to be presented here, but I should at least mention Chris Barker, Arik Cohen, Hans-Martin Gärtner, Andreas Haida, Sophie Repp, Anna Szabolcsi, Hubert Truckenbrodt, and Tom Roeper. Work on this topic is supported by a grant of the Bundesministerium für Bildung und Forschung (BMBF, Förderkennzeichen 01UG0711) to the Zentrum für Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft; the responsibilities remain with the author.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are additional factors that influence the meaning of a complex expressions. First, the meaning of the constituents may be shifted by semantic operators, e.g. the type shift of names to quantifiers in cases like John and every girl (cf. Partee 1987), the aspectual type shift of semelfactives to iterative activities in the light blinked for hours (cf. Moens and Steedman 1988), and metonymic type shifts as in begin the book discussed in Pustejovsky (1995) or the ham sandwich discussed in Nunberg (1977). Second, the linguistic and extra-linguistic context may influence the meaning, as in suppressing implausible interpretations of ambiguous expressions and in specifying the values of variables and indexical expressions. Third, the availability of other expressions in the language may lead to pragmatic optimization, also ruling out certain interpretations that otherwise would be available; e.g. an indefinite noun phrase suggests non-uniqueness as otherwise a definite noun phrase would be used.

  2. 2.

    In naming semantic types, I follow the convention that (σ)τ denotes the type of functions from meanings of type σ to meanings of type τ; if σ is a simple type, parentheses are omitted. Simple types are e for entities and t for truth values; see below for additional simple types.

  3. 3.

    The only argument that Lewis gives is that the sentence-radical view would not allow for a treatment of constituent questions like Who came?, and encouragements like Hurrah for Mary! But this is clearly not the case. Constituent questions can be treated like polarity questions if we assume that their sentence radical denotes a set of propositions or a structured proposition. Encouragements can be seen as speech acts that require a person-denoting referential expression as radical; in our example, hurrah can be treated as an illocutionary operator applied to Mary.

  4. 4.

    Thanks to Hans-Martin Gärtner who directed me towards that paper.

  5. 5.

    In addition, there is a subjunctive form (Konjunktiv I) with special morphology: Maria sagte, dass sie John bewundere and Maria sagte, sie bewundere John. It generally indicates a speaker different from the speaker of the utterance context.

  6. 6.

    In Krifka (2001) I assumed that both types of verbs embed question acts, but that verbs like know type-shift this question act to the set of true answers. This was designed to handle certain phenomena relating to quantification into embedded questions. Now, and even in 2001, I see advantages of the proposal of Krifka (1999); cf. also McCloskey (2005).

References

  • Alston, W. P. (2000). Illocutionary acts and sentence meanings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1961). Ifs and cans. In G. J. Warnock & J. O. Urmson (Eds.), Philosophical papers (pp. 153–180). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Linguistic communication and speech acts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, A., & Krifka, M. (2014). Superlative quantifiers as meta speech acts. Linguistics and Philosophy, 37, 41–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davison, A. (1973). Performatives, felicity conditions, and adverbs. Doctoral dissertation, University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K., & Grandy, R. E. (1999). Conditional assertions and “biscuit” conditionals. Noûs, 33, 405–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emonds, J. E. (1969). Roots and structure-preserving transformations. Doctoral dissertation, MIT, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1986). On bullshit. Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Republished 2005).

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle: L. Nebert.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. S. (2000). Illocutionary force and semantic content. Linguistics and Philosophy, 23, 435–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1984). Studies in the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam: Ms.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1987). Dynamic predicate logic. Towards a compositional, non-representational semantics of discourse. Amsterdam: University of Amsterdam, ITLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. L. (1973). Questions in Montague English. Foundations of Language, 10, 41–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnish, R. M. (2005). Commitments and speech acts. Philosophica, 75, 11–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heycock, C. (2006). Embedded root phenomena. In E. Martin & H. van Riemsdijk (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to syntax (Vol. II, pp. 174–209). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hooper, J., & Thompson, S. (1973). On the applicability of root transformations. Linguistic Inquiry, 465–497.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. A. G. Groenendijk, T. M. V. Janssen, & M. B. J. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (Vol. 135, pp. 277–322). Amsterdam: Mathematical Centre Tracts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1978). Dthat. In C. Peter (Ed.), Syntax and semantics 9 (pp. 221–243). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L. (1974). Presuppositions and linguistic context. Theoretical Linguistics, 1, 181–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, J., & Postal, P. M. (1964). An integrated theory of linguistic descriptions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1999). Quantifying into question acts. In Proceedings of semantics and linguistic theory 9. Cornell: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2001). Quantifying into question acts. Natural Language Semantics, 9, 1–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1970). General semantics. Synthese, 22, 18–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, J. (2005). Questions and questioning in a local English. In Z. Raffaella, H. Campos, E. Herburger, & P. H. Portner (Eds.), Crosslinguistic research in syntax and semantics (pp. 87–126). Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McConnell-Ginet, S. (1982). Adverbs and logical form. Language, 58, 144–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meinunger, A. (2006). On the discourse impact of subordinate clauses. In V. Molnar & S.-s. Winkler (Eds.), The architecture of focus (pp. 459–488). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mittwoch, A. (1977). How to refer to one’s own words: Speech-act modifying adverbials and the performative analysis. Journal of Linguistics, 13, 153–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moens, M., & Steedman, M. (1988). Temporal ontology in natural language. Computational Linguistics, 14, 15–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In J. M. E. Moravcsik, P. Suppes, & K. J. J. Hintikka (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (pp. 221–242). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nunberg, G. (1977). The pragmatics of reference. Doctoral dissertation, City University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogihara, T. (2007). Tense and aspect in truth-conditional semantics. Lingua, 117, 392–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (1987). Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In J. Groenendijk (Ed.), Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers (pp. 115–143). Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1995). The generative lexicon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (1987). Meaning and force. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reis, M. (1997). Zum syntaktischen Status unselbständiger Verbzweit-Sätze. In C. Dürscheid, K. H. Ramers, & M. Schwarz (Eds.), Syntax im Fokus. Festschrift für Heinz Vater (pp. 112–144). Tübingen: Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzi, L. (1997). The fine structure of the left periphery. In H. Liliane (Ed.), Elements of grammar (pp. 281–337). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, J. R. (1970). On declarative sentences. In R. A. Jacobs & P. S. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Readings in English transformational grammar (pp. 222–272). Waltham, MA: Ginn & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sadock, J. M. (1974). Towards a linguistic theory of speech acts. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schreiber, P. A. (1972). Style disjuncts and the performative analysis. Linguistic Inquiry, 3, 3121–3357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R., & Vanderveken, D. (1985). Foundations of illocutionary logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaer, B. (2003). “Manner” adverbs and the association theory: Some problems and solutions. In L. Ewald, C. Maienborn, & C. Fabricius-Hansen (Eds.), Modifying adjuncts (pp. 211–260). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, M. E. A. (2006). Biscuit conditionals: Quantification over potential literal acts. Linguistics and Philosophy, 29, 167–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smaby, R. (1979). Ambiguous coreference with quantifiers. In F. Guenthner & S. J. Schmidt (Eds.), Formal semantics and pragmatics for natural languages (pp. 37–75). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1974). Pragmatic presuppositions. In M. K. Munitz & K. Unger (Eds.), Semantics and philosophy (pp. 197–214). New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staudacher, P. (1987). Zur Semantik indefiniter Nominalphrasen. In B. Asbach-Schnitker & J. Roggenhofer (Eds.), Neuere Forschungen zur Wortbildung und Historiographie in der Linguistik. Festgabe für Herbert E. Brekle zum 50. Geburtstag (pp. 239–258). Tübingen: Narr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenius, E. (1967). Mood and language game. Synthese, 17, 254–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szabolcsi, A. (1982). Model theoretic semantics of performatives. In F. Kiefer (Ed.), Hungarian linguistics (pp. 515–535). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vanderveken, D. (1990). Meaning and speech acts. Vol. I: Principles of language use. Vol. II: Formal semantics of success and satisfaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vendler, Z. (1957). Verbs and times. Philosophical Review, 66, 143–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophische Untersuchungen. London: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Manfred Krifka .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Krifka, M. (2014). Embedding Illocutionary Acts. In: Roeper, T., Speas, M. (eds) Recursion: Complexity in Cognition. Studies in Theoretical Psycholinguistics, vol 43. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05086-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics