Skip to main content

Recursion Restrictions: Where Grammars Count

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Recursion: Complexity in Cognition

Part of the book series: Studies in Theoretical Psycholinguistics ((SITP,volume 43))

Abstract

Since recursion is a fundamental property of human languages, it is puzzling that we regularly find cases where recursion is impossible or restricted. In this paper we argue that these restrictions follow from an independently necessary property associated with individual lexical items, which encodes sensitivity to phonological properties. These restrictions must be stated on the output of the syntactic derivation, when syntactic structures are transferred to phonology as expected in current late spell-out models. The main idea is that phonological properties can be “grafts” on the structure-building requirement of a lexical item, referred to as an epp property, which can then be viewed as a repository of the finely grained knowledge speakers have of the phonological properties associated with local syntactic environments. In this view, restrictions on recursion, though accidental, can be straightforwardly and simply accounted for as arising from the way that independently necessary properties interact in specific local syntactic environments. This accounts for a number of well-known effects, including left branch restrictions, restrictions on center embedding, and complexity effects.

This paper builds on my presentation at the Recursion conference in Amherst, May 2009, and is a substantial revision of my 2010 paper On restricting recursion and the form of syntactic representation lingBuzz/001139. I would like to thank Natasha Abner, Melanie Bervoets, Chris Collins, Uli Sauerland, Ed Stabler, Dominique Sportiche and Anna Szabolcsi, for feedback and comments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Throughout this paper, the question of interspeaker variability arises. Some speakers are perfectly happy with yellower, but others are not. This variability is expected (see Sect. 3 for further discussion), and should make fine predictions about correlating patterns of judgments and systematic interspeaker differences.

  2. 2.

    Comparatively, because we know from decomposition of the VP domain that such transitive structures are in fact syntactically quite large.

  3. 3.

    Richard Kayne (personal communication) finds they homeschooled all their children, they wrongfooted us twice last night, perfectly acceptable. This may imply that the structures in (5a) are different w.r.t. size and perhaps category. The general point made here is that there are differences in the relative sizes of structures and that restrictions on relative sizes can be an arbitrary property of individual heads.

  4. 4.

    Though speakers vary in their tolerance to right-branching relative clauses (e.g. %the queen that you adore’s minister).

  5. 5.

    Other varieties of Hungarian appear to lack such restrictions.

  6. 6.

    The *213 pattern is left out of consideration here. Barbiers (2002) argues this order is universally impossible. Koopman and Szabolcsi (2000, p. 173) list all the conditions that must hold at the same time for a derivation to even yield this pattern. This leads to the expectation that this order will surface very rarely.

  7. 7.

    I have nothing to say about this mysterious fact. It could be a historical accident or perhaps it is not. It seems to also be found in English in the form of the double-ing constraint (Ross 1972). See Appendix 1 for further discussion.

  8. 8.

    Other choices leading to variability depend on the height of merger of functional material and order.

  9. 9.

    See Koopman (2002) for further discussion of problems with the prosodic account in Den Besten and Broekhuis (1989), and the processing account in Broekhuis (1992).

References

  • Barbiers, S. (2002). Book review: Koopman, H. and Szabolcsi A. 2000. Verbal Complexes: Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics, 6, 53–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bresnan, J., & Ford, M. (2010). Predicting syntax: Processing dative constructions in varieties of American and Australian english. Language, 86(1), 168–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broekhuis, H. (1992). Chain government: Issues in Dutch syntax. Leiden: HIL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cinque, G. (1999). Adverbs and functional projections: A cross-linguistic perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • den Besten, H., & Broekhuis, H. (1989). Woordvolgorde in de werkwoodelijke eindreeks. GLOT, 12, 79–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • den Besten, H., & Edmonston, J. (1983). The verbal complex in Continental West Germanic. In W. Abraham (Ed.), On the formal syntax of Westgermania (pp. 155–216). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kayne, R. (1994). The antisymmetry of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kayne, R. (2000). Parameters and universals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kayne, R. (2005). Movement and silence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, H. (2002). Derivations and filters. In A. Alexiadou, E. Anagnostopoulou, S. Barbiers, & H. Gaertner (Eds.), Dimensions of movement: From features to remnants (pp. 151–189). Amsterdam: Benjamins Publications.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, H. (2005a). On the parallelism of DPs and clauses in Kisongo Maasai. In A. Carnie (Ed.), Verb first (pp. 281–303). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, H. (2005b). Korean (and Japanese) morphology from a syntactic perspective. Linguistic Inquiry, 36, 601–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, H. (2006). In defense of the Spec head configuration. In C. Boeckx (Ed.), Agreement systems (pp. 159–199). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, H., & Szabolcsi, A. (2000). Verbal complexes (Current studies in linguistics 34). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longobardi, G. (2001). The structure of DPs. In M. Baltin & C. Collins (Eds.), The handbook of contemporary syntactic theory (pp. 562–604). Malden/Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, N. (2006). A distinctness condition on linearization. ms, MIT. http://web.mit.edu/norvin/www/papers/Distinctness2.pdf

  • Ross, J. (1972). Doubl-ing. Linguistic Inquiry, 3, 61–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sportiche, D. (2005). Division of labor between reconstruction and merge: Strict locality of selection and reconstruction paradoxes. http://ling.auf.net/lingBuzz/000163

  • Szendrői, K., & Tóth, I. (2004). Hungarian verbal clusters: Results of a questionnaire survey. In K. Kíss & H. van Riemsdijk (Eds.), Verb clusters. A study of Hungarian, German and Dutch (pp. 87–121). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, E. (1981). On the notion ‘Lexically related’ and ‘Head of a Word’. Linguistic Inquiry, 8, 101–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wurmbrand, S. (2004). West Germanic verb clusters: The empirical domain. In K. Kíss & H. van Riemsdijk (Eds.), Verb clusters. A study of Hungarian, German and Dutch (pp. 43–87). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hilda Koopman .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix A: A Possible Linearization Account for the Recursion of Infinitives?

Appendix A: A Possible Linearization Account for the Recursion of Infinitives?

We add here a short discussion of Norvin Richards (2006) linearization account. Richards Proposes a general constraint on linearization, which imposes distinctness of linearization of categories within the same phase, a kind of modern incarnation of the OCP, and applies it to doubl-ing. Adapting parts of Kayne’s (1994) LCA, his proposal in essence prohibits two categories within the same phase from being spelled out, because they would yield a conflicting linearization statement. He applies this to a number of different phenomena (distinct markings on DPs, the doubl-ing filter (Ross 1972, but see Koopman 2002 for an explicit proposal along the lines in this paper). Applied to Dutch, this proposal would prohibit the linearization of two infinitives within the same phase, but not across a phase boundary. It is easy to adapt Richards (2006) to Dutch, given the syntactic analysis developed in Koopman and Szabolcsi (2000) and outlined here. Indeed, inverted infinitives end up occurring in the same V+ constituent (hence within the same phase), but infinitives in the VT1 Vinf2 Vinf3 order are each in CPs, hence separated by a phase boundary [C Vinf [C Vinf.. This would allow some understanding as to why Inf is subject to the restriction on recursion but other categories are not, which under the account in this paper is purely a historical accident. However, the proposal does not extend (easily) to any of the other observed and excluded patterns. It will not extend to exclude the 3 1 2 pattern with infinitives in Dutch (*zwemmen wil kunnen), as here the infinitives do not seem to be in the same phase as the selecting infinitive. Nor will it allow a simple understanding of variation, i.e. what happens with Dutch dialects or speakers that allow such patterns, or with German and Hungarian speakers? How do we let the right cases in? If Richards needs Koopman and Szabolcsi (2000) to understand Dutch, the problem then is how to allow German and Hungarian which allow surface constituents of this type. Richards proposal could force a double structural analysis where preverbal infinitives in German and Hungarian are or can be in their own CPs or within smaller constituents, but this would lose all the basic insights of Koopman and Szabolcsi’s analysis (see Koopman and Szabolcsi for an argument against this option), and any hope to model the observed variability between individual grammars. This analysis will have nothing to say about the Hungarian cases where it seems you can invert twice but not three times, and where the restriction on recursion does not seem sensitive to a particular category, just to dept of embedding in a specific location. And finally, it will have nothing to say about other cases of restrictions on recursion, and the general notion of [+ph] size that is independently needed, and that seems widely applicable.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Koopman, H. (2014). Recursion Restrictions: Where Grammars Count. In: Roeper, T., Speas, M. (eds) Recursion: Complexity in Cognition. Studies in Theoretical Psycholinguistics, vol 43. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05086-7_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics