Skip to main content

Aristotle’s Buddhism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Aristotle's Theory of Abstraction

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 73))

  • 917 Accesses

Abstract

Many of Aristotle’s theoretical terms, like ‘form’, ‘actuality ’, ‘substance’ and ‘cause ’, have the formal features of relations: they have correlatives, and statements about them have the conversion that Aristotle finds characteristic of relata . This is no accident: in this way Aristotle can treat, say, the form of an individual substance as if it were a being in its own right without the danger of relapsing into Platonism . Moreover, as substance alone does not have this co-dependence on its accidents, thereby it has primacy of being. Understand the ‘accidents’ here as ‘individual accidents ’, like ‘this-here whiteness’. This quality does not exist; rather its concrete paronym , ‘this-here white’ does, but only as a complex of the individual quality with the substance.

Universals are parts of individuals. Certain universals constitute their essences, as the genus animal is a constituent of the individual substance Socrates . No universal is a substance; even genera and species are so only secondarily. Likewise, the matter and form of an individual substance may constitute it, but only as its parts, which cannot exist independently, qua parts. Still, like relata , they may be treated as if they were independently. Abstract paronyms like rationality exist only in substances where they form complexes with them so as to produce the correlative concrete paronyms .

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I find it ironic for them to have the name ‘predicable’ at all. For Aristotle does not recognize them in his list of predications (“categories”).

  2. 2.

    Still cf. Metaphysics 1040b16–1040b27; Simplicius , in Phys . 463, 7–9 on ‘principle’.

  3. 3.

    The distinction is between what is complete and what is incomplete. Cf. Brown 1986: 68–9. See Owen 1957: 172–3 for a fuller discussion of this distinction and its later history in the early Academy. Cf. Frede 1967: 16–29. Reeve 1985: 54–5, surveys different interpretations of ‘’ and ‘’, and finds two main camps: (1) the distinction amounts to that between a one-place and a two-place predicate [Cornford , Malcolm , Vlastos ] (2) “the complement of the verb ‘to be’ either does not import something different from the subject, or does import something different from the subject [Owen , Frede , Heinaman , Reeve ].” See too Bostock 1984, nn. 2 & 20, on the secondary literature.

  4. 4.

    Take ‘relational ’ along the lines of Barwise and Moss 1996: 12: A set R is a relation if every element of R is an ordered pair. Relational structures are “pairs (A,R), such that A is a set, and B is a relation on R.” A function (or map) is “a set f of ordered pairs with the property that if <a,b> and <a,c> belong to f, then b = c.” “For any sets c and d, there is a set → d of all functions from c to d.”

  5. 5.

    As discussed in Chap. 3, there is a problem with categories like position, action and passion. These seem fully relational . Indeed some commentators subsume them under relation .

  6. 6.

    I generally accept the Owen -Frede account of an accident being in a subject where an accident is not a part of its definition and cannot exist independently of it. See Owen 1965; Frede 1987.

  7. 7.

    Aristotle takes what has primacy to have priority . Cf. Cat. 2b3–6; Metaph. 1019a1–4; Peramatzis 2011.

  8. 8.

    See Chaps. 3 and 4 for the complexities for the relata .

  9. 9.

    Cf. the use of ‘accident’ in Metaphysics V.7.

  10. 10.

    Some senses of parts that he distinguishes concern only quanta , and I leave them aside here. [Metaph. 1023b12–5; 1023b32–4; 1052b17–22; 1052b31–5] See Bäck 2010. I shall focus on substances and on his distinction between structured wholes and unstructured totalities . Koslicki (2008: 122–5) champions some of Aristotle’s views on parts today.

  11. 11.

    Simplicius , in Phys . 551, 32–3: “Also every genus is predicated synonymously of all the species, but the whole only of the homoiomeres, and of those not in virtue of being a whole.”

  12. 12.

    Aristotle does distinguish these two cases. Perhaps the difference with the prior sense comes from ‘nose’ not being strictly a constituent, the genus or differentia , of the definition of ‘snubness’.

  13. 13.

    He has more extensive discussions of these distinctions of wholes also when he discusses ‘one’ in V.6 and X.1.

  14. 14.

    However Simplicius suggests that the whole is the totality of its parts for intelligible substances having no partitioning while it is not that totality for corporeal things. [in Phys . 560, 32–561, 10]

  15. 15.

    Harte 2002: 279. “…the identification of this wooden object as a chair leg is in some way dependent on the role it could play in the constitution of a chair.” Here there is an ontological and not an epistemological dependence.

  16. 16.

    However Fine (1993: 21, n. 6) says that Plato did not use ‘universal’ and ‘particular’ thus and that Aristotle invented these uses of these terms.

  17. 17.

    Offhand ‘universal’ and ‘individual’ () or ‘singular’ (‘) do not seem relational : they do not fit well into Aristotle’s conversion scheme: *‘a singular is a singular of some universal’; ‘an individual is an individual of some universal’. Here the English may obscure. Or, rather, Aristotle might be using ‘singular’ to emphasize the primacy of individual substances over universals. ‘Individual’ has a more complicated history as it is tied to Plato ’s account of division: an individual is something that cannot be differentiated further by more universals.

  18. 18.

    Bäck 2000: 178–85. Frege objects to this strenuously, as it confuses the UF and UO relations.

  19. 19.

    This, perhaps, is the point that Howard Robinson (1983: 129) is trying to make—obscurely! (Nussbaum 1984: 207)—about the relation of body and soul , the matter and form of a human being: “it is not the man who is the sailor who stands to the boat as form to matter, but the man qua sailor. The individual substance , the man, can exist without a boat, but the man qua sailor exists as such only from his relation to the boat.”

  20. 20.

    Because they are parts.

  21. 21.

    Aristotle recognizes no prime matter : so too Charlton 1970; Cohen 1996: 55–100.

  22. 22.

    Lewis (1991) at times comes dangerously close to this position, and says (279–81) that the end product ends up being something with three dimensions. Charlton (1970: 138) and Schofield (1972: 97–101) do not. Still Lewis (1991: 151) ends up saying that Aristotle makes forms the primary substances . Cf. Loux 1991: 12, n.4; Inciarte 2005 on Lewis 1991: 196ff., especially 197, n. 45.

  23. 23.

    Despite the efforts of Joan Kung et al., Aristotle rejects the claim that the substance is not predicated of matter in Metaphysics VII.3. See Bäck 2000: 87–96.

  24. 24.

    Owens (1981: 35–40) suggests: not ‘the matter is a stone’ but perhaps ‘the matter is lapidized’.

  25. 25.

    So too Lorenz (2006: 151, n. 3) suggests that Aristotle thinks of the “parts of the souls” as aspects—to avoid there being more than one soul .

  26. 26.

    Here I take ‘potentiality ’ in a general sense, as in Metaphysics V.12; IX.1: not that of motion but perhaps of change taken broadly. So too Frede 1994: 184; Beere 2009: 55. Kosman (1984: 128) recognizes two different senses.

  27. 27.

    We might dispute this. Still Aristotle assumes a correspondence between what we can know in the past and what is possible, as is evidenced in his principle of plenitude.

  28. 28.

    Spontaneous generation will present a problem, the same as the one about the potentiality of the rock to fall.

  29. 29.

    Some complications arise in the modal syllogistic.

  30. 30.

    From this Kosman (1984: 123) claims that the kinesis-energeia distinction is the key to understanding Aristotle’s ontology.

  31. 31.

    Cf. Bäck 2003.

References

  • Anagnostopoulos, A. (2011). Senses of Dunamis and the structure of Aristotle’s Metaphysics Θ. Phronesis, 56, 388–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bäck, A. (1995). Aristotelian necessities. History and Philosophy of Logic, 16(1), 89–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bäck, A. (2000). Aristotle’s theory of predication. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bäck, A. (2003). Avicenna on relations and the Bradleyan regress. In J. Biard & I. Rosier-Catach (Eds.), La tradition médiévale des Catégoires (pp. 69–84). Louvain: Peeters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bäck, A., s.v. Aristotle in the Handbook of mereology; Repr. as “Aristotle’s theory of parts”, Munich, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Moss, L. S. (1996). Vicious circles. Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beere, J. (2009). Doing and being. An interpretation of Aristotle’s Metaphysics theta. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostock, D. (1984). Plato on ‘is not’. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 2, 89–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostock, D. (Trans. & Comm.). (1994). Aristotle’s Metaphysics Z and H. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowin, J. (2008). Aristotle on identity and persistence. Apeiron, 41(1), 63–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, L. (1986). Being in the Sophist: A syntactical enquiry. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 4, 49–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. (1979). Notes on book zeta of Aristotle. Oxford: Sub-faculty of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charles, D. (1988). Aristotle on hypothetical necessity and irreducibility. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 69, 1–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlton, W. (1970). Did Aristotle believe in prime matter? In J. L. Ackrill & L. Judson (Eds.), Aristotle: Physics books I and II (pp. 129–145). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. M. (1996). Aristotle on nature and incomplete substance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. M. (2009). Aristotle’s Metaphysics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/

  • Cooper, J. (1987). Hypothetical necessity and natural teleology. In A. Gotthelf & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 243–274). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Corkum, P. (2008). Aristotle on ontological dependence. Phronesis, 53(1), 65–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, G. (1984). Separation. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 2, 31–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, G. (1985). Separation: A reply to Morrison. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 3, 159–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, G. (1993). On ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, M. (1967). Prädikation und Existenzaussage (Vol. 18). Göttingen: Vandenhoeck u. Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, M. (1987). Individuals in Aristotle. In Essays in ancient philosophy (pp. 49–71). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, M. (1994). Aristotle’s notion of potentiality in Metaphysics Q. In T. Scaltsas, D. Charles, & M. L. Gill (Eds.), Unity, identity, and explanation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics (pp. 173–194). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, M., & Patzig, G. (1988). Aristoteles Metaphysik Z (2 Vols.). Munich: C.H. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harte, V. (2002). Plato on parts and wholes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Inciarte, F. (2005). On Aristotle’s theory of substance. In L. Flamarique (Ed.), First principles, substance and action. Hildesheim: Olms.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irwin, T. (1988). Aristotle’s first principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2008). On the structure of objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kosman, L. A. (1984). Substance, being, and Energeia: The argument of Metaphysics theta. In Oxford studies in ancient philosophy (Vol. 2, pp. 121–149). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, F. A. (1991). Substance and predication in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, H. (2006). The brute within. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loux, M. J. (1991). Primary Ousia. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menn, S. (1994). The origins of Aristotle’s concept of energeia: energeia and dunamis. Ancient Philosophy, 14, 73–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Modrak, D. K. W. (2001). Aristotle’s theory of language and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, D. (1985). Separation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 3, 125–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1984). Aristotelian dualism: A reply to Howard Robinson. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 2, 197–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen, G. E. L. (1957). A proof in the Peri Ideon. The Journal of Hellenic Studies, 77, 103–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owen, G. E. L. (1965). Inherence. Phronesis, 10(1), 97–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owens, J. (1981). Matter and predication. In J. R. Caton (Ed.), Aristotle, the collected papers of Joseph Owens (pp. 35–40). Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peramatzis, M. (2011). Priority in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, C. D. C. (1985). Motion, rest, and duality in the Sophist. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophic, 67, 47–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, C. D. C. (2000). Substantial knowledge: Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, H. (1983). Aristotelian dualism. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 1, 123–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, M. (1972). Metaphysics Ζ3: Some suggestions. Phronesis, 17, 97–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spellman, L. (1995). Substance and separation in Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waterlow [Broadie], S. (1982). Nature, change, and agency in Aristotle’s physics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt, C. (2003). Ways of being. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yu, J. (2003). The structure of being in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bäck, A. (2014). Aristotle’s Buddhism. In: Aristotle's Theory of Abstraction. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 73. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04759-1_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics