Skip to main content

Social Justice in Practice

  • Chapter
Social Justice in Practice

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 14))

  • 914 Accesses

Abstract

It is not uncommon to argue that political philosophy should have much more practical relevance than it actually has [1]. As Alan Hamlin and Zofia Stemplowska write in their paper on ideal theory, there are many who think that a “key problem of political philosophy” is its “relative unwillingness to provide solutions to urgent problems facing people here and now; or for people as they are rather than as they should be” [2]. If philosophers really want to say something useful about concrete matters such as ongoing preparation of laws, they need to have detailed information about a number of factual issues. This is one reason why political philosophy should have close connections to social sciences [3] and why political philosophers should undertake causal analyses of social processes [4]. To take seriously the idea that political philosophy should have an action-guiding character, here and now, is to accept that philosophers should take into account facts such as existing public opinion and its effects on the feasibility of alternative policy options [5]. As Pablo Gilabert and Holly Lawford-Smith write, “when we think about whether a proposal might succeed, it seems crazy not to factor in citizens’ resistance” [6].

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. I would like to thank Joseph Almog, Luca Barlassina, Thomas Magnell, Andrew Mason, Jani Sinokki, Saul Smilansky, Susanne Uusitalo, and Federico Zuolo for their helpful comments. I would also like to thank Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen for a valuable discussion. For a view that political philosophy should have much more practical relevance than it actually has, see e.g. Geuss, R.: Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2008). Cf. Galston, W.A.: Realism in Political Theory. European Journal of Political Theory 9, 385–411 (2010), esp. 404–405; Brennan, G., Pettit, P.: The Feasibility Issue. In: Jackson, F., Smith, M. (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy, pp. 258–279. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2005). For a discussion, see e.g. Waldron, J.: Political Political Philosophy. The Journal of Political Philosophy 21, 1–23 (2013).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Hamlin, A., Stemplovska, Z.: Theory, Ideal Theory and the Theory of Ideals. Political Studies Review 10, 48–62 (2012), esp. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  3. For a discussion, see e.g. Miller, D.: Political Philosophy for Earthlings. In: Leopold, D. (ed.) Political Theory: Methods and Approaches, pp. 29–48. Oxford University Press, Cary (2008), esp. 43; Goodin, R.E., Pettit, P.: Introduction. In: Goodin, R.E., Pettit, P. (eds.) A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, pp. 1–4. Blackwell, Oxford (1995). See also Shapiro, I.: Problems, Methods, and Theories: What’s Wrong with Political Science and What to Do about It? In: White, S.K., Moon, J.D. (eds.) What Is Political Theory?, pp. 193–216. Sage, London (2004). Shapiro (p. 193) argues: ”The specialization that has divided political philosophy from the rest of political science has been aided and abetted by the separation of normative from empirical political theory, with political philosophers declaring a monopoly over the former while abandoning the enterprise of ‘positive’ political theory to other political scientists. This seems to me to have been bad for both ventures”.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Wiens, D.: Demands of Justice, Feasible Alternatives, and the Need for Causal Analysis. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16, 325–338 (2013).

    Google Scholar 

  5. David Miller argues that political proposals should be ”reasonably acceptable for present-day citizens”, but he distinguishes between ”political feasibility” (feasibility of the kind that concerns practical politicians) and feasibility constraints of political philosophy. Miller: Political Philosophy for Earthlings, 46–47. The same distinction is made in Räikkä, J.: The Feasibility Condition in Political Theory. The Journal of Political Philosophy 6, 27–40 (1998).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Gilabert, P., Lawford-Smith, H.: Political Feasibility: A Conceptual Exploration. Political Studies 60, 809–825 (2012), esp. 813. See also Gilabert, P.: The Feasibility of Basic Socioeconomic Human Rights: A Conceptual Exploration. The Philosophical Quarterly 59, 659–681 (2009). Gilabert argues that “the feasible set of political reforms [...] is partly shaped by the empirical and normative beliefs” (p. 680).

    Google Scholar 

  7. The criticism can be interpreted in many ways. Perhaps the point is simply to say that political theories should be sensitive to human limits and take into account our motivational restrictions.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Simmons, A.J.: Ideal and Nonideal Theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs 38, 5–36 (2010), esp. 19. My intention is not to imply that Simmons defends feasibility arguments.

    Google Scholar 

  9. William A. Galston was President Clinton’s Deputy Assistant for Domestic Policy from 1993 to 1995, which suggests that philosophers can be helpful.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For a discussion, see e.g. Swift, A.: The Value of Philosophy in Nonideal Circumstances. Social Theory and Practice 34, 363–387 (2008), esp. 365.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Brennan, G., Pettit, P.: The Feasibility Issue, 258–279; Lægaard, S.: Feasibility and Stability in Normative Political Philosophy: The Case of Liberal Nationalism. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9, 399–416 (2006); Jensen, M.: The Limits of Practical Possibility. The Journal of Political Philosophy 17, 168–184 (2009); Lawford-Smith, H.: Understanding Political Feasibility. The Journal of Political Philosophy 21, 243–259 (2013).

    Google Scholar 

  12. A brief characterization of ”feasibility” should suffice here, although it is an important concept in my discussion. Cf. Wiens, D.: Prescribing Institutions Without Ideal Theory. The Journal of Political Philosophy 20, 45–70 (2012), esp. 56, fn. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Brennan, G., Southwood, N.: Feasibility in Action and Attitude. In: Rønnow-Rasmussen, T., et al. (eds.) Hommage à Wlodek, pp. 1–25 (2007), esp. 9 (December 15, 2013), http://www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek.

  14. Lawford-Smith, H.: Feasibility Constraints for Political Theories. A Doctoral Thesis, ch. 5. Australian National University (2010); Gilabert, P.: Feasibility and Socialism. The Journal of Political Philosophy 19, 52–63 (2011), esp. 57–58.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cf. Cowen, T.: The Importance of Defining the Feasible Set. Economics and Philosophy 23, 1–14 (2007), esp. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Lægaard: Feasibility and Stability in Normative Political Philosophy: The Case of Liberal Nationalism, 406; Räikkä: The Feasibility Condition in Political Theory, 32–34; Gilabert, Lawford-Smith: Political Feasibility: A Conceptual Exploration, 813.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cohen, G.A.: The Pareto Argument for Inequality. Social Philosophy and Policy 12, 160–185 (1995), esp. 172.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cohen, G.A.: Incentives, Inequality, and Community. In: Petersen, G.B. (ed.) The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Volume Thirteen. University of Utah Press, Salt Lake City (1992). Cf. Cohen: Incentives, Inequality, and Community, 311. See also Lægaard: Feasibility and Stability in Normative Political Philosophy: The Case of Liberal Nationalism, 404; Williams, A.: Incentives, Inequality, and Publicity. Philosophy & Public Affairs 27, 225–247 (1998), esp. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cf. Barry, B.: Culture & Equality, pp. 36–37. Polity, Cambridge (2001).

    Google Scholar 

  20. This description of the notion of feasibility may raise objections. As mentioned, people do not agree what “feasibility” means, and it may turn out that various understandings of the concept are equally acceptable. However, the argument that follows should not be dependent on any particular conception of feasibility. As I see it, all plausible conceptions are acceptable.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. Cohen: Incentives, Inequality, and Community, 262–329; Cohen: The Pareto Argument for Inequality, 160–185. See also Cohen, G.A.: Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 26, 3–30 (1997); Cohen, G.A.: If You’re an Egalitarian, How Come You’re So Rich? Harvard University Press, Cambridge (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cohen: Incentives, Inequality, and Community, 288–290, 311; Cohen: The Pareto Argument for Inequality, 172–174.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cohen: Incentives, Inequality, and Community, 290, fn. 17. Cohen argues that habits can change, ”if not always at the level of the individual, then certainly at the social level, through reformed structures of education”.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cohen: The Pareto Argument for Inequality, 184.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cohen: Incentives, Inequality, and Community, 301.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See however Lægaard: Feasibility and Stability in Normative Political Philosophy: The Case of Liberal Nationalism, 399–416. For a critical remarks on Cohen, see e.g. Williams: Incentives, Inequality, and Publicity, 225–247; Shaw P.: The Pareto Argument and Inequality, The Philosophical Quarterly 49, 353–368 (1999). For a reply, see Cohen, G.A.: Rescuing Justice & Equality, ch. 8. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (2008).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Obviously, the addition of feasibility arguments would increase the importance of social sciences in political argumentation.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. Cohen’s example concerning British academics in Incentives, Inequality, and Community, 284. The claim that “nurses cannot use” certain arguments should be understood as a claim that the use of those arguments would not confirm the norms of the discussion.

    Google Scholar 

  29. I am not claiming that the feasibility argument in question cannot be an argument at all if presented by the nurses. Rather, it seems to be an argument that falls short of norms that should govern public debate (cf. note 28).

    Google Scholar 

  30. For a critical discussion, see e.g. Brian Barry: Culture & Equality, p. 35. Polity, Cambridge (2001).

    Google Scholar 

  31. For a discussion, see e.g. Bayertz, K.: Four Uses of Solidarity. In: Bayertz, K. (ed.) Solidarity, pp. 3–28. Kluwer, Dordrecht (1999).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf. Cohen’s discussion in Incentives, Inequality, and Community, 291, fn. 18. See also 294, fn. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. Austin, J.L.: How to Do Things with Words. Harvard University Press, Harvard (1975); Austin, J.L.: Performative Utterances in his Philosophical Papers, pp. 220–239. Oxford University Press, London (1970). For a discussion, see e.g. Anderson, J.S.: How to Define “Performative”. Libertryck, Uppsala (1975). Perhaps the spokeswoman could say that “Nurses will move if their wages are frozen” without making a threat, if she says it in the role of a researcher at a workshop of sociologists – behind closed doors.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Here is an example. An environmental activist can use a feasibility argument in the following form: “It would be good to improve the employment by investing in the mining industry. However, improving employment by investing in the mining industry is impossible and hence not feasible without taking considerable environmental risks. Therefore, the government should not improve employment conditions by investing in the mining industry.”

    Google Scholar 

  35. For a relatively hostile attitude toward standard political philosophy, see e.g. Geuss: Philosophy and Real Politics.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Kant, I.: On the Common Saying: This May Be True in Theory, But It Does Not Apply in Practice. In Reiss, H. (ed.) Kant’s Political Writings, p. 89. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1977); originally published in Berlinische Monatsschrift 22, 201–284 (1793), as Uber den Gemeinspruch: Das Mag in der Theorie richtig sein, taugt aber nicht fur die Praxis.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Swift, A., White, S.: Political Theory, Social Science, and Real Politics. In: Leopold, D. (ed.) Political Theory: Methods and Approaches, pp. 49–69. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008), esp. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  38. On the task of political philosophy, see e.g. Baier, K.: Justice and the Aims of Political Philosophy. Ethics 99, 771–790 (1989); Leonard, S.: How Not to Write about Political Theory. Political Theory 17, 101–106 (1989); Stears, M.: The Vocation of Political Theory. European Journal of Political Theory 4, 325–350 (2005); Sen, A.: What Do We Need from a Theory of Justice. The Journal of Philosophy 103, 215–238 (2006).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Räikkä: The Feasibility Condition in Political Theory, 30.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Swift, White: Political Theory, Social Science, and Real Politics, 55.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Cf. Nagel, T.: Equality and Partiality, pp. 22–23. Oxford University Press, New York (1991). For a discussion, see Smilansky, S.: Moral Demands, Moral Pragmatics, and Being Good. Utilitas 22, 303–308 (2010).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Estlund, D.M.: Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework, p. 267. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2008).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Arendt, H.: Truth and Politics, The New Yorker (February 25, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Rawls, J.: Reply to Habermas. The Journal of Philosophy 92, 132–180 (1995), esp. 174–175.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Cf. Cohen, J.: For a Democratic Society. In: Freeman, S. (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, pp. 86–138. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2003), esp. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  46. For a review of the debate, see e.g. Laden, A.S.: The Justice of Justification. In: Finlayson, J.G., Freyenhagen, F. (eds.) Habermas and Rawls: Disputing the Political, pp. 135–152. Routledge, New York (2011), esp. 151–152.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Rawls: Reply to Habermas, 174–175. Italics added.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Simmons: Ideal and Nonideal Theory, 19.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Questions of feasibility may even be beside the point, if the idea is to determine our ultimate moral convictions about the content of justice without too much concern about practical issues. See Cohen, G.A.: Facts and Principles. Philosophy & Public Affairs 31, 211–245 (2003), esp. 242. Cohen argues that “political philosophy is a branch of philosophy”, and one cannot reduce the value of philosophy to its possible practical relevance. See also Mason, A.: Just Constraints. British Journal of Political Science 34, 251–268 (2004).

    Google Scholar 

  50. Donald Moon, J.: The Current State of Political Theory. In: White, S.K., Moon, J.D. (eds.) What Is Political Theory?, pp. 12–29. Sage, London (2004), esp. 27.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juha Räikkä .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Räikkä, J. (2014). Social Justice in Practice. In: Social Justice in Practice. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 14. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-04633-4_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics