Skip to main content

The Articulation of a Scientific Domain from the Viewpoint of Hermeneutic Phenomenology: The Case of Vectorial Metabolism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Multidimensionality of Hermeneutic Phenomenology

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 70))

Abstract

By making use of an approach stemming from hermeneutic phenomenology, this paper explores the constitution of meaningful objects in the domain of vectorial biochemistry. At stake are both theoretical objects related to anisotropic processes of trans-membrane transport and objects of inquiry contextually ready to hand within a configuration of scientific practices. The concept of the hermeneutic fore-structure of scientific research is discussed. The domain’s formal, conceptual and experimental articulation gets fore-structured in the horizon of possibilities projected by the interrelated practices. The appropriation of possibilities constitutes meaningful objects. Some basic trends of the domain’s articulation are addressed through analyzing three aspects of interpretative fore-structuring.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Kockelmans strongly distinguishes his Heideggerian interpretation of the mythical understanding from the established mythological paradigms in cultural anthropology and the phenomenology of religion. The disclosure of the world’s totality of meaning within the mythical mode of Being does not demand a narrative that relates the time of the historical events to the pre-historical time of origins, or a narrative that is capable to found rites. In fact, Kockelmans’s conception is closer to Bultmann’s program of demythologization which aims at revealing the primary mythical horizon of religious imagery. It is the existential interpretation of the Holy Script that reveals this horizon.

  2. 2.

    In analyzing the way in which Heidegger spells out the expression “to let be” with regard to scientific discovery and the formulation of scientific laws, John Haugeland reaches the conclusion that “it is little odd to say that the law of gravity was not true before Newton discovered it… And there remains the question of what to say about Einstein’s discovery that there is (was and will be) no force of gravity—just curved space-time. Does this mean that, through Newton, his laws became true, but only for a while?” (Haugeland 2007, 100) In my view, the way in which Haugeland formulates and tries to address and settle such questions indicates a naturalist treatment of Heidegger’s claim that there is (scientific) truth only so long and so far as Dasein is. Because of the situated transcendence of Dasein-as-epistemic-subject (and the finitude of all ontic knowledge) the theoretical formulations known as scientific laws are always already hermeneutically fore-structured. It is this hermeneutic fore-structuring that Haugeland does not take into consideration in his interpretation of Heidegger’s claim. An additional shortcoming of this interpretation is the avoidance of the distinction between ontic/epistemic and ontological truth. On the alternative interpretation I am going to subscribe in this essay, each scientific law is true within a characteristic hermeneutic situation that reveals and conceals the objectified world in a specific manner.

  3. 3.

    In its classical formulation this paradigm is to be found in Heidegger (1927/1962, 188–203). The basic concepts here are the “fore-structure of understanding” and the “as-structure of interpretation.” The interplay between the fore-structure qua horizon of possibilities and the as-structure qua ongoing articulation of meaningful units takes on the form of hermeneutic circle. The hermeneutic-phenomenological analysis of a particular interrelatedness of practices (like the practices in a domain of scientific research) requires an interpretation of the way in which the hermeneutic circle operates in articulating the domain disclosed by that interrelatedness of practices.

  4. 4.

    With regard to the catalysis of solute transport of specific molecules across lipid membranes this conclusion is drawn for the first time by Davson and Danielli (1943), pp. 72–79. This classical work is also the pioneering study of the thermodynamic aspects of the vectorial processes of cellular physiology, in particular processes running against the concentration gradient.

  5. 5.

    Fore-having, fore-sight, and fore-conception are three relationships between fore-structure of understanding and as-structure of interpretation. In other words, they are three characteristics of the hermeneutic circle which operates in the articulation of a domain disclosed by an interrelatedness of practices. See also Kockelmans (1986).

  6. 6.

    Rheinberger commits this claim also to a “dialectic of fact and artifact” taking place in the constitution of the scientific research’s “epistemic things”.

  7. 7.

    There is a long history of sociological, historical, and philosophical reconstructions (case studies) of Mitchell’s chemiosmotic hypothesis and the subsequent ox-phos controversy. At the beginning of this history is Gilbert and Mulkay’s (1984) study designed in terms of a sociological discursive analysis. The significant value of this study is due to the way in which the authors make use of interviews with 34 participants in the ox-phos controversy. The historical reconstruction of Allchin (1997) presents not only the genesis of Mitchell’s hypothesis, but also a quite vivid picture of the development of the chemical theory. Weber’s (2002a, b) nice philosophical reconstructions of Mitchell’s research program and its experimental verifications (a reconstruction that takes into consideration also the problematic of incommensurability) try to evaluate the positions in the ox-phos controversy in terms of normative epistemology, whereas Prebble (2001) investigates in a highly original manner the role of the “personal knowledge and tacit knowing” (in the sense of Michael Polanyi’s conception) in the formation of Mitchell’s philosophical and scientific views.

  8. 8.

    Mitchell indicates that Malcolm Dixon in his 1941 lecture course at Cambridge had presented for the first time the notion of group transfer as a spatial migration of a donor group to an acceptor group. For Mitchell, however, Dixon had been not committed to the view of a vectorial mechanism of group translocation. Nevertheless, the very vectorial representation of diagrams of enzymes had been of great importance for Mitchell’s orientation toward vectorial chemistry. (See Prebble and Weber 2003, 35)

  9. 9.

    Initially, it was a hypothesis that mitochondria ejected protons and that proton gradient drives ATP synthesis. It had been introduced as an explanatory mechanism of the coupling of electron transport to phosphorylation. What was challenged by this hypothesis was the view that transport and metabolism were essentially separate processes. As an experimentally verified theory the chemiosmotic one concerns the process of energy conservation in mitochondrial and bacterial respiration and in photosynthesis. Its main cellular object of inquiry is the inner membrane where is the site of the enzyme ATPase for ATP synthesis. It is important to be indicated that chemiosmotic theory was regarded by Mitchell as a special case of nowadays is called “vectorial metabolism.” Yet Prebble (2001), 447 is right when stressing that “the notion of vectorial metabolism is given its most fulsome treatment almost concurrently with promulgation of the chemiosmotic theory.” The linkage between the coupled reactions catalyzed by two osmoenzymes depends on the electrochemical potential gradient generated by one reaction and consumed by the other.

  10. 10.

    See, in particular Prebble and Weber (2003, p. 3), Weber (2002b), Mulkay and Gilbert (1984), Skulachev (1987). This view is supported even by Slater (2003), one of Mitchell’s major opponents.

  11. 11.

    Hermeneutic phenomenology of scientific research is to be distinguished from the studies of the hermeneutic pre-understandings of individual scientists. Prebble (2001) provides an excellent example of such a study in which at issue are Mitchell’s philosophical pre-understandings as tacit knowledge. The author manages to show how the philosophical concept of fluctoid underlies as a tacit element the development of Mitchell’s formulation of the chemiosmotic hypothesis and its verification as a theory. The hermeneutic fore-structure of scientific research has a trans-subjective status, and accordingly cannot be regarded as belonging to the personal knowledge. Fore-having, fore-sight, and fore-conception are not to be attributed to the tacit (including collective) knowledge as well.

  12. 12.

    Another aspect of the text’s openness is to be spelled out in terms of Rheinberger’s conception where the semiotic aspect of constituting “epistemic things” in scientific research is presented as constant creation in the research process of inscriptions, traces, and graphematic articulations. In this perspective, textualazing amounts to creating not a codified text, but a textual whole of traces—production of traces within the deferring spaces of representation engendered by the configuration. Thus, the text is intimately related to what Rheinberger calls a tracing game. For him, in scientific research there is a permanent replacement of any presumed signified by signifier (Rheinberger 1997, 104). What is read in a certain space of representation takes its meaning not from things that are beyond the research process but from what is read in other spaces of representation. Within a configuration of scientific practices as readable technologies the potentially endless production of traces becomes foreseeable. It is this fore-sight that makes the totality of what gets read in a configuration a relatively homogeneous (but by no means a structurally codified) text. Following further Rheinberger’s characterization, it is a text without “referent” and without assignable “origins.” Furthermore, it is a text that is doomed to be radically recast and re-contextualized in new configurations of scientific practices.

  13. 13.

    A theoretical object is projected upon a horizon of research possibilities when the ongoing actualization of these possibilities in various contexts of research contributes to visualizing contextually the properties ascribed to the object by the respective theory.

  14. 14.

    Actually, the interpretations of the dualist nature led to articulation of objects of inquiry that transcended the scope of the domain of vectorial biochemistry. Allchin (1997, 22) is absolutely right when reaching the conclusion that however strong the domain of vectorial biochemistry became emancipated, “Mitchell’s alternative theory and experimental gestalt did not wholly eclipse all aspects of the chemical hypothesis or its domain. Many of the findings that initially led biochemists to search for the intermediates were ‘composted’ into other areas of research practice or domains that are not addressed by the chmiosmotic model.”

References

  • Allchin, D. 1996. Cellular and theoretical chimeras: Piecing together how cells process energy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 27: 31–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. 1997. A twentieth-century phlogiston: Constructing error and differentiating domains. Perspectives on Science 5: 81–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Claude, A. 1946. Fragmentation of mammalian liver cells by differential centrifugation: II. Experimental procedures and results. Journal of Experimental Medicine 84: 61–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, J.A. 2005. Mechanisms of morphogenesis. Burlington/San Diego/London: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davson, H., and J.F. Danielli. 1943. The permeability of natural membranes. Cambridge: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, G.N., and M. Mulkay. 1984. Opening Pandora’s box. A sociological analysis of scientists’ discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginev, D. 2008. Cognitive existentialism. The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly 57: 227–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, B.C., and L.E.H. Trainor. 1985. Tip and whorl morphogenesis in Acetabularia by calcium-regulated strain-fields. Journal of Theoretical Biology 117: 79–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, D.E. 1965. Oxidative phosphorylation. Essays in Biochemistry 1: 91–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harold, F.M. 1990. To shape a cell: An inquiry into the causes of morphogenesis in microorganisms. Microbiological Reviews 54: 381–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harold, F.M. 1991. Biochemical topology: From vectorial metabolism to morphogenesis. Bioscience Reports 6: 347–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. 2007. Letting Be. In Transcendental heidegger, eds. S. Crowell and J. Malpas, 93–103. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heelan, P. 1983. Natural science as hermeneutic of instrumentation. Philosophy of Science 50: 181–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heelan, P. 1998. Scope of hermeneutics in the philosophy of natural science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29: 273–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1927/1962. Being and Time. Trans. J. Macquarrie, and E. Robinson. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, Joseph. 1986. On the hermeneutic dimension of the natural sciences. Etudes Phénoménologique 3: 33–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, Joseph. 1993. Ideas for a hermeneutic phenomenology of the natural sciences. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Larkum, A.W.D. 2003. Contributions of Henrik Lundegårdh. Photosynthesis Research 76: 105–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehninger, A. 1960. Oxidative phosphorylation in submitochondrial systems. Federation Proceedings 19: 952–962.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lundegårdh, H. 1945. Absorption, transport and exudation of inorganic ions by the roots. Arkiv för Botanik 32: 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. 1961. Biological transport phenomena and the spatially anisotropic characteristics of enzyme systems causing a vector component of metabolism. In Membrane transport and metabolism, ed. A. Kleinzeller and A. Kotyk, 22–34. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. 1962. Metabolism, transport and morphogenesis: Which drives which? Journal of General Microbiology 29: 25–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. 1967. Translocations through natural membranes. Advances in Enzymology and Related Areas of Molecular Biology 29: 33–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. 1972. Chemiosmotic coupling in energy transduction: A logical development of biochemical knowledge. Journal of Bioenergetics 3: 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. 1975. The protonmotive Q cycle: A general formulation. FEBS Letters 59: 137–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. 1976. Possible molecular mechanisms of the protonmotive function of cytochrome systems. Journal of Theoretical Biology 62: 327–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P. 1991. Foundations of vectorial metabolism and osmochemistry. Bioscience Reports 11: 297–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, P., and J. Moyle. 1958. Group translocation: A consequence of enzyme-catalysed group transfer. Nature 182: 372–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nuccitelli, R. 1988. Ionic currents in morphogensesis. Experientia 44: 657–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orgel, L.E. 1999. Are you serious, Dr. Mitchell? Nature 402: 17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prebble, J. 2001. The philosophical origins of Mitchell’s chemiosmotic concepts. Journal of the History of Biology 34: 433–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prebble, J., and B. Weber. 2003. Wandering in the gardens of the mind. Peter Mitchell and the making of glynn. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quagliariello, E., S. Papa, F. Palmieri, E.C. Slater, and N. Siliprandi (eds.). 1976. Electron transfer chains and oxidative phosophorylation. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg. 1997. Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saier, M.H. 2000. Vectorial metabolism and the evolution of transport systems. Journal of Bacteriology 182: 5029–5035.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skulachev, V. 1987. Introduction to the Russian Edition of G. N. Gilbert and M. Mulkay’s Opening Pandora’s box. Moscow: Progress. 9–11. (In Russian)

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater, E.C. 1953. Mechanism of phosphorylation in the respiratory chain. Nature 172: 975–978.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slater, E.C. 2003. Metabolic gardening. Nature 422: 816–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, B. 1991. Glynn and the conceptual development of the chemiosmotic theory: A retrospective and prospective view. Bioscience Reports 11: 577–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. 2002a. Theory testing in experimental biology: The chemiosmotic mechanism of ATP synthesis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33: 29–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. 2002b. Incommensurability and theory comparison in experimental biology. Biology and Philosophy 17: 155–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, L. 1969. Positional information and the spatial pattern of cellular differentiation. Journal of Theoretical Biology 25: 1–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dimitri Ginev .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ginev, D. (2014). The Articulation of a Scientific Domain from the Viewpoint of Hermeneutic Phenomenology: The Case of Vectorial Metabolism. In: Babich, B., Ginev, D. (eds) The Multidimensionality of Hermeneutic Phenomenology. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 70. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01707-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics