Skip to main content

God or Ultimate Reality in Theory and Practice: A Philosophical Analysis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Meditation – Neuroscientific Approaches and Philosophical Implications

Part of the book series: Studies in Neuroscience, Consciousness and Spirituality ((SNCS,volume 2))

Abstract

The present chapter explores how human experiences, including experiences of God or Ultimate Reality should be understood in relation to reality. It is suggested that experiencing is the sine qua non of human existence. It is argued that human beings cannot not experience. Experiences are real in the sense that they have causal effects on the brain, and the cultural-religious-personal environment in which human beings are embedded. Also a distinction is made between concepts, conceptions and conceiving. In order to answer the question how human experiences can be justified, two principles or criteria are adapted (1) The experience should have de facto evidence and (2) it should have effective evidence. In order to answer the question how such experiences should be understood during the course of interdisciplinary research, four main types of naturalism are analyzed, ontological, methodological, epistemological naturalism and supernaturalism. The result of the analyses suggests that a minimalist coherent ontological naturalism or an extended or flexible interferential ontological naturalism should be adapted. Finally, the problem of the gap between descriptive and normative claims is considered.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In a previous article I made a distinction between being as sein and being as ein Wesen – a being. (Runehov 2006, p. 62). I put human between brackets because to be an experiencer does not only apply to human beings.

  2. 2.

    The difference between concept and conception derives from philosopher Herrmann (2008).

  3. 3.

    One could perhaps argue in a similar way concerning time.

  4. 4.

    This also counts for gravitation and what is hypothesized as the graviton.

  5. 5.

    I do not believe I have to go into this any further - our own experiences and what we experience through media channels have sufficiently clarified and convinced us of this matter of fact.

  6. 6.

    I changed “man’s” into “human’s”.

  7. 7.

    My italics.

  8. 8.

    What I refer to as minimalist ontological naturalism should not be confused with Griffin’s idea that naturalism can be understood in a minimal or maximal sense (Griffin 2000) 11–12. What I mean by minimalist naturalism is a naturalism useful within a specific realm or scope of inquiry.

  9. 9.

    Where “v” stands for “inclusive v”.

  10. 10.

    What I refer to as minimalist ontological naturalism should not be confused with Griffin’s idea that naturalism can be understood in a minimal or maximal sense (Griffin 2000, pp. 11–12). What I mean by minimalist naturalism is a naturalism useful within a specific realm or scope of inquiry.

  11. 11.

    Rottschaefer: my italics. Drees calls his ontological naturalism supernaturalistic religious naturalism. Furthermore, Drees defends the view of a physically closed universe.

  12. 12.

    The difference between 1. and 2. is, while 1. says that all P (apples) are Q (green); 2. says that it is only within the realm R (Uppsala) that all P (apples) are Q (green). This is not the same as saying that “some P are Q”, because this would say that there are apples that are green here and there (there is no specific realm where all apples are green).

  13. 13.

    Tomas Hançil as quoted by Spurway, N. “Evolutionary Epistemology”, forthcoming in The Encyclopedia of Science and Religions, Springer, 2010/2011.

  14. 14.

    My italics.

  15. 15.

    Interference: as in Physics where the term means: The variation of wave amplitude that occurs when waves of the same or different frequency come together. In other words, the meeting of two waves (sound, light, etc.) which reinforce or neutralise each other according to their relative phases on meeting (depending on whether they are in or out of phase).

  16. 16.

    Inspired by Ward (2005, pp. 210–211).

References

  • Ashbrook, J.B. 1996. Interfacing religion and the neurosciences: A review of twenty-five years of exploration and reflection. Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science 31(4): 545–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burns, Charlene P.E. 2002. Divine becoming: Rethinking Jesus and incarnation. Minneapolis: Ausburg Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, P., and A. Peacock (eds.). 2004. In whom we live and move and have our being. Cambridge/Michigan: Eerdmans Publishers Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drees, W.B. 1996. Religion, science, and naturalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Drees, W.B. 2003. Naturalism. In The encyclopedia of science and religion, ed. W. Van Huyssteen, 593–597. New York: Macmillan Library Reference.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drees, W.B. 2010. Religion and science in context: A guide to the debates. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. [1931] 2006. The world as I see it. New York: Citadel Press Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. 2006. The varieties of naturalism. In The Oxford handbook of religion and science, ed. P. Clayton and Z. Simpson, 432–452. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. 1999. Naturalism. In The cambridge dictionary of philosophy, ed. R. Audi, 596–599. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, D.R. 2000. Religion and scientific naturalism: Overcoming the conflicts. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guttenplan, S. (ed.). 2001. A companion to the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, E. 2004. Religion, reality and a good life: A philosophical approach to religion. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, E. 2008. On the distinction between the concept of God and conceptions of God. International Journal of Philosophy of Religion 64: 63–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs J. 2008. Naturalism. Resource document. The internet encyclopedia of philosophy. www.iep.utm.edu/naturali/. Accessed 15 June 2010.

  • Jeeves, M. 2006. Human nature: Reflection on the integration of psychology and christianity. West Conshohocken: Templeton Foundation Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, M. 1989. Mind, brain & the quantum. The compund ‛I’. Cambridge, MA/Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newberg, A.B., and E. d’Aquili. 2001. Why God won’t go away. New York: Ballantine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oviedo, L. 2007. Has theology anything to suggest to consciousness studies? In Herausforderungen und Grenzen wissenshaftlicher Modelle in Naturwissenschaft und Theologie, ed. F. Vogelsang and H. Meisinger, 125–140. Bonn: Evangelische Akademie im Rheinland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. 2007. Naturalism. Resourse document. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism. Accessed 15 June 2010.

  • Persinger, M. 1993. Vectorial cerebral hemisphericity as differential sources for the sensed presence, mystical experiences and religious conversions. Perceptual and Motor Skill 76: 915–930.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1981. Reason, truth and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O. 1960. Word and object. Cambridge, MA: M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rottschaefer, W.A. 2001. Emerging naturalism: William Rottschaefer and Willem Drees in converstation: How to make Naturalism Safe for Supernaturalism: An evalutation of Willem Drees’s Supernaturalistic Naturalism. Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science 36(3): 407–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Runehov, A.L.C. 2006. A being or to be? Philosophical thoughts about future research on neuroscience and religions and the need for interdisciplinarity. European Journal of Science and Theology 2(1): 55–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Runehov, A.L.C. 2007. Sacred or neural? The potential of neuroscience to explain religious experience. Götingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.P. [1943] 1992. Varet och intet. Göteborg: Korpen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, F.F. 2005. Naturalism. In A companion to metaphysics, ed. J. Kim and E. Sosa, 343–345. Malden/Oxford/Victoria: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. [1818] 1992. Världen som vilja och föreställning. Nora: Nya Doxa

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenmark, M. 2001. Scientism: Science, ethics and religion. Hants: Ashgate Science and Religion Series.

    Google Scholar 

  • Underhill, E. 1912. Mysticism, a study in the nature and development of man’s spiritual consciousness. New York: E.P. Dutton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walach, H., and A.L.C. Runehov. 2010. The epistemological status of transpersonal psychology: The data-base argument revisited. Journal of Consciousness Studies 17(1–2): 145–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, A. 2005. Defending ethical naturalism: The roles of cognitive science and pragmatism. Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science 40(1): 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1973. Philosophical investigations. New Jersey: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yandell, K. 1993. The epistemology of religious experience. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebksi, L.T. 1998. Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebksi, L.T. 2004. Divine motivation theory. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The present has been made possible with the supported by the Copenhagen University Star Research Program “Naturalism and Christian Semantics” at the Copenhagen University.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anne L. C. Runehov Th.D., MPhil .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Runehov, A.L.C. (2014). God or Ultimate Reality in Theory and Practice: A Philosophical Analysis. In: Schmidt, S., Walach, H. (eds) Meditation – Neuroscientific Approaches and Philosophical Implications. Studies in Neuroscience, Consciousness and Spirituality, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01634-4_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics