Skip to main content

From Features via Frames to Spaces: Modeling Scientific Conceptual Change Without Incommensurability or Aprioricity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Frames and Concept Types

Part of the book series: Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy ((SLAP,volume 94))

Abstract

The (dynamic) frame model, originating in artificial intelligence and cognitive psychology, has recently been applied to change-phenomena traditionally studied within history and philosophy of science. Its application purpose is to account for episodes of conceptual dynamics in the empirical sciences (allegedly) suggestive of incommensurability as evidenced by “ruptures” in the symbolic forms of historically successive empirical theories with similar classes of applications. This article reviews the frame model and traces its development from the feature list model. Drawing on extant literature, examples of frame-reconstructed taxonomic change are presented. This occurs for purposes of comparison with an alternative tool, conceptual spaces. The main claim is that conceptual spaces save the merits of the frame model and provide a powerful model for conceptual change in scientific knowledge, since distinctions arising in measurement theory are native to the model. It is suggested how incommensurability as incomparability of theoretical frameworks might be avoided (thus coming on par with a key-result of applying frames). Moreover, as non(inter-)translatability of world-views, it need not to be treated as a genuine problem of conceptual representation. The status of laws vis à vis their dimensional bases as well as diachronic similarity measures are (inconclusively) discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “In the Ray taxonomy, for example, the attributes beak and foot are not independent. There are correlations between the value of beak and that of foot: webbed feet are usually associated with a round beak, and clawed feet with a pointed beak. These are physical constraints imposed by nature: webbed feet and round beaks are adapted to the environment in which water-birds live, but clawed feet and pointed beaks would be a hindrance in water. Because of these constraint relations, the attributes beak and foot must be used together as a cluster in classification” (Chen 2002, p. 6).

  2. 2.

    “Influenced by Darwin’s evolutionary theory, ornithologists realized that many morphological characters used as classification standards in previous taxonomies were arbitrary, and they began to search for new classification criteria that could display the origins of birds” (Chen 2002, p. 12).

  3. 3.

    “Consequently, communication obstacles were bound to occur between the followers of the two systems. The followers of the Ray taxonomy, for example, would regard ‘grallatores’ from the Sundevall taxonomy as incommensurable, because they could not find an equivalent native term with referents that do not overlap those of the foreign one. Both ‘water-bird’ and ‘land-bird’ from the old taxonomy overlap ‘grallatores,’ which includes water-birds like herons as well as landbirds like storks. On the other hand, the followers of the Sundevall taxonomy would regard ‘water-bird’ from the Ray taxonomy as confusing, because they could not find an equivalent native term without violating the non-overlap principle. Sundevall’s ‘natatores’ overlaps Ray’s ‘waterbird’; specifically, the former is included by the latter, but they are not in species-genus relations” (Chen 2002, p. 9).

  4. 4.

    Since F = ma holds, some values can be inferred, e.g., for the three force dimensions.

References

  • Adams, B., and M. Raubal. 2009. A metric conceptual space algebra. In Spatial information theory. Proceedings of the 9th international conference, COSIT 2009, in Aber Wrac’h, France, September 2009, Lecture notes in computer science 5756, eds. Stewart Hornsby, K., C. Claramunt, M. Denis, and G. Ligozat, 51–68. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aisbett, J., and G. Gibbon. 2001. A general formulation of conceptual spaces as a meso level representation. Artificial Intelligence 133: 189–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H., and N. Nersessian. 2000. Nomic concepts, frames, and conceptual change. Philosophy of Science 67: S224–S241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H., P. Barker, and X. Chen. 1996. Kuhn’s mature philosophy of science and cognitive psychology. Philosophical Psychology 9: 347–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H., P. Barker, and X. Chen. 2006. The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, P., X. Chen, and H. Andersen. 2003. Kuhn on concepts and categorization. In Thomas Kuhn, ed. T. Nickles, 212–245. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. 1992. Frames, concepts, and conceptual fields. In Frames, fields, and contrast, ed. A. Lehrer and E.F. Kittay, 21–74. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L., and C.R. Hale. 1993. Components of conceptual representation: From feature list to recursive frames. In Categories and concepts: Theoretical views and inductive data analysis, ed. I. Van Mechelen, J. Hampton, R. Michalski, and P. Theuns, 97–144. San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R.W. 2003. The devil in the details: Asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction, and emergence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berka, K. 1983. Measurement: Its concepts, theories, problems, Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 72. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botteril, G. 2007. Review of Andersen, H., P. Barker, and X. Chen. 2006. The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://www.ndpr.nd.edu. Accessed July 2011.

  • Chen, X. 1997. Thomas Kuhn’s latest notion of incommensurability. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 28: 257–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, X. 2002. The ‘Platforms’ for comparing incommensurable taxonomies: A cognitive-historical analysis. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 33: 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, X. 2003. Object and event concepts: A cognitive mechanism of incommensurability. Philosophy of Science 70: 962–974.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, X. 2005. Transforming temporal knowledge: Conceptual change between event concepts. Perspectives on Science 13: 49–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, X., and P. Barker. 2000. Continuity through revolutions: A frame-based account of conceptual change during scientific revolutions. Philosophy of Science 67: S208–S223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, X., H. Andersen, and P. Barker. 1998. Kuhn’s theory of scientific revolutions and cognitive psychology. Philosophical Psychology 11: 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decock, L. 2006. A physicalist reinterpretation of ‘phenomenal’ spaces. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 5: 197–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diez, J.A. 1997a. A hundred years of numbers. A historical introduction to measurement theory 1887–1990. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 28: 167–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diez, J.A. 1997b. A hundred years of numbers. A historical introduction to measurement theory 1887–1990. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 28: 237–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. 2005. Why are most laws of nature mathematical? In Nature’s principles, ed. J. Faye, P. Needham, U. Scheffler, and M. Urchs, 55–75. Amsterdam: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 2001. Dynamics of reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 2002. Kant, Kuhn, and the rationality of science. Philosophy of Science 69: 171–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 2008. History and philosophy of science in a new key. Isis 99: 125–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. 2000. Conceptual spaces. The geometry of thought. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadow, H. 1892. On the classification of birds. Proceedings of the Zoological Society of London 1892: 229–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P., and F. Zenker. 2010. Using conceptual spaces to model the dynamics of empirical theories. In Belief revision meets philosophy of science, ed. E.J. Olsson and S. Enqvist, 137–153. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P., and F. Zenker. 2013. Theory change as dimensional change: Conceptual spaces applied to the dynamics of empirical theories. Synthese 190: 1039–1058.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hand, D.J. 2004. Measurement theory and practice. London: Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H.V. 1887. Zahlen und Messen erkenntnistheoretisch betrachtet. In Schriften zur Erkenntnistheorie, Helmholtz, H.V. 1920, 70–109. Berlin: Springer (trans: Helmholtz, H.V. in Counting and Measuring, 1930, 72–114. Princeton: Van Noestrand).

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. 2009. Let me briefly indicate why I do not find this standpoint natural. Einstein, general relativity and the contingent a priori. In Discourse on a new method. Reinvigorating the marriage of history and philosophy of science, ed. M. Domski and M. Dickson, 333–355. Chicago/La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. 1993. Reconstructing scientific revolutions. Thomas S. Kuhn’s philosophy of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krantz, D.H., R.D. Luce, P. Suppes, and A. Tversky. 1971/1989/1990. Foundations of measurement. Vols. I–III. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1970. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1983. Commensurability, comparability, and communicability. In PSA 1982, vol. II, ed. P. Asquith and T. Nickles, 669–688. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1993. Afterwords. In World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science, ed. P. Horwich, 311–341. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuukkanen, J.-M. 2006. Meaning change in the context of Thomas S. Kuhn’s philosophy. Dissertation, University of Edinburgh. http://hdl.handle.net/1842/1259. Accessed July 2011.

  • Labov, W. 1973. The boundaries of words and their meanings. In New ways of analyzing variation in English, ed. C.J. Bailey and W.W. Shuy, 340–373. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCann, H.G. 1978. Chemistry transformed: The paradigm shift from phlogiston to oxygen. Norwood: Ablex Publishing Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minsky, M. 1975. A framework for representing knowledge. In The psychology of computer vision, ed. P. Winston, 211–277. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munsell, A.H. 1915. Atlas of the Munsell color system. Boston: Wadsworth-Howland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N.J. 1995. Opening the black box: Cognitive science and history of science. Osiris 10: 195–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raubal, M. 2004. Formalizing conceptual spaces. In Formal ontology in information systems. Proceedings of the third international conference (FOIS 2004), vol. 114, ed. A. Varzi and L. Vieu, 153–164. Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ray, J. 1678. The ornithology of Francis Willughby. London: John Martyn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E., C.B. Merris, W.D. Gray, D.M. Johnson, and P. Boyes-Braem. 1976. Basic objects in natural categories. Cognitive Psychology 8: 382–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P.K. 2008. Review of Andersen, H., P. Barker, and X. Chen. 2006. The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. British Journal for the History of Science 41: 116–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, S.S. 1946. On the theory of scales of measurement. Science 103: 677–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sundevall, C. 1889. Sundevall’s Tentamen. London: Porter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, J.R. 2003. Linguistic categorization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 1999. How scientists explain disease. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 2009. Review of Andersen, H., P. Barker, and X. Chen. 2006. The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60: 843–847.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, B., and K. Hemenway. 1984. Objects, parts, and categories. Journal of Experimental Psychology. General 113: 169–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. 1989. Structural realism. Dialectica 43: 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank the organizers of CTF 09, the editors of this volume and two anonymous reviewers, as well as Laurence Barsalou, Peter Gärdenfors, Joel Parthemore, Gerhard Schurz, Gregor Strle and Ionnis Votsis for support, insightful comments, and criticism. Research was funded by the Swedish Research Council (VR).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frank Zenker .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zenker, F. (2014). From Features via Frames to Spaces: Modeling Scientific Conceptual Change Without Incommensurability or Aprioricity. In: Gamerschlag, T., Gerland, D., Osswald, R., Petersen, W. (eds) Frames and Concept Types. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol 94. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01541-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics