Skip to main content

What Kind of Ethics? – How Understanding the Field Affects the Role of Empirical Research on Morality for Ethics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Empirically Informed Ethics: Morality between Facts and Norms

Part of the book series: Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy ((LOET,volume 32))

Abstract

Today, many ethicists are wont to display a certain reticence and skepticism toward new empirical psychological and neurobiological research into moral behavior. The reasons for this are manifold. The first is almost certainly to be found in the widespread view that ethics is concerned with normative questions, as well as the examination of moral language and the logical structure of moral arguments. Empirical research on morality seems incapable of making any contribution here. A second reason has to do with the excessive aspirations and expectations linked by some authors to this type of research, which come close to a “naturalization” of morality and ethics. Third, such research frequently raises the question of whether what is being experimentally examined as “morality” is not in fact based on models that are far too simple, ones that might relate to a pretheoretical everyday comprehension of morality, but that do not grasp the phenomenon in the differentiating approach adopted by ethicists. The most important reason, however, is the fact that findings from state-of-the-art empirical research on morality run counter to a perception of ethics characterizing large parts of modern ethical thinking. According to this perception, the task of ethics is to justify moral judgments rationally (i.e., argumentatively), deeming that moral judgments can be rationally justified. An obvious tension exists between this view and empirical moral research findings stating that moral evaluations are based on the emotional evaluation of actions or situations. If, namely, moral evaluations develop in this way, then they cannot be demonstrated to a third party argumentatively. Rather, the morally right or wrong can only show itself to a third party when that party takes a close look at the action or situation in question and evaluates it emotionally. Current empirical moral research therefore raises the challenge of subjecting a widely accepted view of ethics to a critical reappraisal. This is what the following will attempt. I shall proceed by, first, examining the arguments used to validate the comprehension of ethics as a rational justification of morality, in order to expose their untenability against a background of the current empirical findings on morality. I shall then ask what types of reasons are encountered within morality and how they differ from arguments. Finally, I shall advocate the theory that rather than providing a rational justification of moral judgments, ethics has the far more modest task of guiding us toward correct moral thinking that does justice to moral phenomena.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    An example is Casebeer (2003: 843): “The goal of naturalized ethics is to show that norms are natural and that they arise from and are justified by purely natural processes”.

  2. 2.

    Unless stated otherwise, in the following I shall use the expression ‘rational’ in the sense of argumentative rationality, as distinct from purposive rationality (cf. Höffe 1984).

  3. 3.

    From this Birnbacher deduces an argument against particular ethics (e.g., Christian ethics). Namely, these types fail to satisfy a claim to general validity (cf. Birnbacher 1991: 113).

  4. 4.

    Cf. the contributions in Bleisch and Schaber (2007).

  5. 5.

    This debate is expounded in Ammann (2007).

  6. 6.

    It may be tempting to object that even arguments can have a motivating force. Anyone with a compulsive reason for an action thus has sufficient grounds to carry out that action. Indeed, he has sufficient grounds as far as his reasons are concerned, but this does not mean that he has sufficient grounds for actually carrying out the action. It is possible to have sufficient grounds for an action and still not carry it out, due to a lack of motivation or some inner resistance. Moral reasons are characterized by the fact that what is focused upon here as a reason. For example, “my wife was really ill” has a simultaneously motivating effect because the matter in question is experienced and evaluated emotionally (moral internalism). This implies that people whose emotional skills are restricted (e.g., because of brain damage) not only suffer from a lack of motivation, but are also incapable of having moral reasons (Fischer 2010). They may be able to think logically and subsume situations under rules, but they do not have at their disposal the skill of moral cognition, or cognition that is emotionally evaluating.

  7. 7.

    In meta-ethics this leads into the debate about the relationship between moral and natural attributes. This debate reveals that an automatic consequence of the objectification of morality is a naturalism, in the sense that a moral value (right/wrong, good/bad, moral status, thick moral concepts) is ascribed to natural attributes. Accordingly, values supervene on constellations of natural attributes. What is questionable about this way of thinking is that it creates a sufficient condition from a necessary one. To compare: light waves must have a certain wavelength in order for us to perceive the colour ‘red’. But redness is not already given with this wavelength of light independently of our perception. Likewise one can say that a specified behaviour needs to show particular natural attributes in order to be able to be experienced or perceived as cruel. But cruelty is not given with these attributes. It is independent of how we experience or perceive and thus emotionally evaluate behaviour. Emotional evaluation is directed toward experienced reality, as distinct from the objectified, descriptively broached reality to which talk of ‘natural attributes’ refers. This means that moral value, to the extent that it is based on emotional evaluation, is also not given independently of our experience. Therefore, it cannot be given with something that is obviously independent of it, namely with natural attributes. This does not lead us to conclude that moral value is “merely subjective.” We can communicate intersubjectively about whether or not an action is cruel. We can do this because the word ‘cruel’ is the linguistic articulation of a (perceptional) pattern which we have jointly internalised via language. It refers, as we have said, to experienced reality, and we can recognise it in many individual actions. The sufficient condition for an action to be cruel is that it refreshes this pattern which, in turn, presupposes certain natural attributes as a necessary condition in order for actions to be able to be perceived within the framework of this pattern.

  8. 8.

    On how to treat and evaluate a moral problem like active euthanasia in the light of the concept of ethics represented here, cf. Fischer (2009).

References

  • Ammann, C. 2007. Emotionen – Seismographen der Bedeutung. Ihre Relevanz für eine christliche Ethik. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbacher, D. 1991. Sind wir für die Natur verantwortlich? In Ökologie und Ethik, ed. ibid., 103–139. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbacher, D. 2003. Analytische Einführung in die Ethik. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bleisch, B., and P. Schaber (eds.). 2007. Weltarmut und Ethik. Paderborn: Mentis-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casebeer, W.D. 2003. Moral cognition and its neural constituents. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 4(10): 840–846.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Düwell, M. 2008. Bioethik. Methoden, Theorien und Bereiche. Stuttgart/Weimar: Metzler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. 2009. Warum überhaupt ist Suizid ein ethisches Problem? Über Suizid und Suizidbeihilfe. Zeitschrift für Ethik in der Medizin 55: 243–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. 2010. Grundlagen der Moral aus ethischer Perspektive und aus der Perspektive der empirischen Moralforschung. In Die Struktur der moralischen Orientierung. Interdisziplinäre Perspektiven, ed. ibid., S. Gruden, 19–48. Berlin: LIT-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1981. Theorie kommunikativen Handelns, Vol 1 Handlungsrationalität und gesellschaftliche Rationalisierung. Vol. 2. Zur Kritik der funktionalistischen Vernunft. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Höffe, O. 1984. Sittlichkeit als Rationalität des Handelns? In Rationalität. Philosophische Beiträge, ed. H. Schnädelbach, 141–174. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1751. An enquiry concerning the principles of morals. Publ. for A Millar Online see David Hume, D Banach, St Anselm College. http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/Hume-Enquiry%20Concerning%20Morals.htm#sec1. [German version: Hepfer, K. (ed.). 2002. Eine Untersuchung der Grundlagen der Moral. Göttingen: Vandenhoek & Ruprecht].

  • Nida-Rümelin, J. 2006. Theoretische und angewandte Ethik: Paradigmen, Begründungen, Bereiche. In Angewandte Ethik. Die Bereichsethiken und ihre theoretische Fundierung, ed. ibid., 2–85. Stuttgart: Alfred Kröner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prichard, H.A. 1912. Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake? Mind 21: 21–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quante, M. 2003. Einführung in die Allgemeine Ethik. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rippe, K.P. 1998. Ethikkommissionen als Expertengremien? In Angewandte Ethik in der pluralistischen Gesellschaft, ed. ibid. Freiburg: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaber, P. 2003. Menschenwürde als das Recht, nicht erniedrigt zu werden. In Menschenwürde – Annäherung an einen Begriff, ed. R. Stoecker, 119–131. Wien: ÖBV + HPT Verlagsgesellschaft GmbH.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. 2007. Hunger, Wohlstand und Moral. In Weltarmut und Ethik, ed. B. Bleisch and P. Schaber, 37–52. Paderborn: Mentis-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. 1989. Sources of the Self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tugendhat, E. 1984. Antike und moderne Ethik. In Probleme der Ethik, ed. ibid. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. 1987. Who is my neighbour? In Trying to make sense, ed. ibid, 154–166. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

This text has been translated by Sarah L. Kirkby, B.A. Hons.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johannes Fischer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fischer, J. (2014). What Kind of Ethics? – How Understanding the Field Affects the Role of Empirical Research on Morality for Ethics. In: Christen, M., van Schaik, C., Fischer, J., Huppenbauer, M., Tanner, C. (eds) Empirically Informed Ethics: Morality between Facts and Norms. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy, vol 32. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01369-5_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics