Skip to main content

The Mechanism of the Form-Content Correlation Process in the Paradigm of Socio-Natural Sciences

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perspectives on Linguistic Pragmatics

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 2))

Abstract

In this chapter, I search for the mechanism correlating linguistic form with content in order to explain (in the sense of the word ‘explain’ used in empirical, i.e., natural and modern social sciences) how sentence meaning contributes to the utterance meaning. I do that against the background of two currently dominating positions on that issue: minimalism and contextualism. Minimalists regard language as a self-standing abstract system and claim that only weak pragmatic effects are involved in interpreting sentences. Contextualists believe that language can be described adequately only within a theory of language understanding and that strong pragmatic effects are also involved in interpreting sentences. The resultant controversy, presented in Sect. 1, has been pronounced by Michel Seymour the most important one in the 20th century. I begin Sect. 2 with Mario Bunge’s argument that since abstract systems cannot change by themselves and only speakers of language do, an explanatory theory of language (one looking at language from the perspective of empirical (socionatural) sciences) must concern language understanding, i.e., view language as a bio-psycho-social phenomenon. However, language understanding needs to be incorporated in the theory of language in a more fundamental way than current contextualist models do. These models assume the existence of language as self-standing, abstract structure with a list of symbol-reference pairings (Such assumption is legitimate as long as one regards such an abstraction as only a methodological device.) and model language understanding disregarding its psycho-social development process. Such assumptions, however, lead to a number of insurmountable problems. I conclude Sect. 2 by arguing that to solve these problems, as well as to be consistent with the evidence attesting to the fact that language self-organizes and self-regulates, (also reviewed in this section,), we need a model of language understanding and production to be coined within a developmental bio-psycho-social perspective. In Sect. 3, I propose a specific model of the form-meaning correlation process, based on a novel mechanism of a linguistic categorization, which is compatible with a bio-psycho-social developmental perspective advocated in Sect. 2. On this view, the utterance meaning is dependent both on the approximate conventional meaning of the construction components conveying it, and on the specific social function of the whole construction (a relevant pragmeme), which identifies feasible situation specific contents. The given construct selects one out of these options. I finish the chapter, Sect. 4, by preliminarily testing the mechanism of the form-content correlation process introduced in Sect. 3 both qualitatively and quantitatively to meet the methodological standards of empirical sciences.

Languages thrive in the hospitable environment of human brains and communities

Hurfort

Words do not suffice to express my gratitude to Professor Alessandro Capone for his continuous intellectual stimulation, constructive criticism, and help of all sorts in fostering my intellectual efforts. I would also like to thank deeply Professor Jacob Mey for helping me communicate my thoughts in the form publishable in the Journal of Pragmatics as well as for directing my attention to the social dimension of language via his concept of pragmeme. My special appreciation goes also to prof. Gabriel Altmann for the attention he has been giving to my research, to whom I owe the idea of the role of natural-like selection in language self-organization and self-regulation, as well as gratitude for his immense kindness and encouragement. Last, but not least, I would like to thank especially deeply Professor Hélène Włodarczyk and Professor André Włodarczyk for stimulating my thoughts with their MIC theory, as well as inviting me to participate as an invited speaker in the 3rd MIC workshop on the methodology of language studies at CELTA, Sorbonne, 2012.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    after Altmann (1978).

  2. 2.

    of which we know very little, as recently acknowledged by Recanati (2011).

  3. 3.

    Consequently Recanati (2011) rightly questions the sense of the very division into descriptive adjectives and adjectives requiring “filling in”.

  4. 4.

    Other researchers expressing similar views include: Capone (2005, 2006 and later), Carston (2002), Levinson (2000), Mey (2001, Recanati (2004, 2011), Searle (1983), Sperber and Wilson (1986), Stainton (2006a) and Travis (2001).

  5. 5.

    The sentence was overheard on a TV show.

  6. 6.

    The debate between contextualists and minimalists covers a very similar terrain that the divide between Cartesian and non-Cartesian linguistics does as proposed in a research of Kopytko (1995, 1998, 2001a, b, 2004).

  7. 7.

    Recursive rules were probably first proposed to capture linguistic compositionality in Ajdukiewicz’s (1935) categorical grammar. The idea of recursiveness has been popularized in linguistics, however, through Chomsky’s generative rules, starting with Chomsky (1957).

  8. 8.

    approximately speaking.

  9. 9.

    The theory of Universal Grammar requires the existence of an organ in the brain hosting UG that had evolved before language did. This, however, is evolutionary implausible.

  10. 10.

    The artificial and natural assemblies can also combine. The process of book production starting form farming trees can serve as an example.

  11. 11.

    I use the term ‘functional sentence’ to refer to a sentence with a specific illocutionary force.

  12. 12.

    This argument is no longer valid if we transfer the burden of making economic choices from an individual to a natural selection process taking place in a community.

  13. 13.

    Strictly speaking, Zipfian distribution could also be the result of a relatively simple, statistical processes. Yet, along with the information about the hierarchical structure of the object of study and the processes involved, establishing power laws relating some characteristics of that object is enough to indicate its self-organizing origin.

  14. 14.

    Ants when walking, leave scent on the trail. The group of ants in search of food that has found the shortest route will cover the distance between their anthill and that source of food the largest number of times, making that trail most smelly. A new group of ants which has just left the anthill to search for food, will chose the most smelly path, which is the shortest one.

  15. 15.

    I use the term “conventional” here in the sense of some sort of representation which is an average of the individual representations of the same functional category in a given linguistic society. .

  16. 16.

    Bunge (2003) opposes an integral structure, such as the one present in a cardiovascular system, to a combinatory structure, such as that present in a car. While the latter one was put together from parts, the former one evolved by subsequent evolutionary steps and cannot be substituted fully by plastic elements. It is integrally related to all other elements in a human body and specific history of evolution. .

  17. 17.

    This view may remind of 19th century concepts in linguistics, but here, language is not viewed as an independent organism. The “organism” considered here is not the semiotic system per se, but a linguistic community with the semiotic system (language) being an aspect of its behavior.

  18. 18.

    For instance, the Polish for guinea pig is “swinka morska” (literally: a sea piglet), which animal, of course, is neither a pig, nor has anything to do with marine life.

  19. 19.

    The core meaning can be defined as the part which is statistically “significant”. This is done in elementary particle physics, when identifying short living particles (it is possible to give statistically an approximate cut off point and state what is ‘core’).

  20. 20.

    This hypothesis is motivated by Sachs (1967) in Grzybek (2006), while Luther and Fenk (1984) in Grzybek (2006) further showed that this strategy operates under “normal condition” i.e. when there is no motivation to concentrate on the form.

  21. 21.

    Another interesting proposal crossing the boundary of semantics in the process of interpreting language in a novel way is Distributive Grammar proposed by Andre and Helene Włodarczyk, cf. www.celta.paris-sorbonne.fr/anasem/indexASMIC.html.

  22. 22.

    An early version of the present model appeared in Zielinska (1997, 1999).

  23. 23.

    The members of the Fife Graces Group, the proponents of the thesis that language is a Complex Adaptive System view, are, among others, Clay Beckner of the University of New Mexico, Richard Blythe, Edinburgh University, Joan Bybee, University of New Mexico, Morten, H Christensen, University of Cornell, William Croft, Universityu of New Mexico, John Holland Santa Fe Institute, Nick N. Ellis, University of Michigan, and others.

  24. 24.

    in Bunge’s (2003) understanding of the concept ‘system’.

  25. 25.

    Those conversant in Polish are advised to see Grabińska (1993, 1994, 1998) for especially illuminating presentation of the relation between models, theories, and reality.

  26. 26.

    Linguistic research employing analogical modeling introduced by Skousen, puts me in that second camp.

  27. 27.

    Until the precision arrived at is sufficiently good and further increase in the precision of encoded lexemes (or their intended content) does not increase the functionality of language.

  28. 28.

    Encoded value is understood as a statistical average of past values.

  29. 29.

    What needs to be made clear here is the definition of the terms “categorizing” and “relative”. By a categorizing adjective I mean one which when applied to the noun results in the selection of a distinct subcategory. For instance ‘a blue crayon’ differences from ‘a red crayons’ in colour only thus the adjectives red and blue as used in the examples above are not categorizing. On the contrary, the adjective high when modifying the noun chair selects ‘a high chair’, which item has a number of characteristics (including its novel function) singling out the subcategory of ‘high chairs’ from among all chairs, therefore the adjective high in the phrase high chair can be termed ‘categorizing’. By ‘a relative adjective’, in turn I mean one whose actual value depends on the range of the given property in the items modified with it. For instance, the value of an adjective big changes depending whether it modifies a star or a mouse.

  30. 30.

    One more, intuitively better way to try when CLO-ing ‘semantic closeness’ would be to consider the actual frequency of the occurrence of specific collocates, and not the number of types, as Wulf did.

  31. 31.

    At the same time when I published my results, Tabakowska (2007) also published a study concerning the ordering the adjectives in Polish. Tabakowska, however does not consider any hard frequency based evidence, but carries out a purely intuition based (cognitive) analysis of meaning of selected AAO phrases. She concludes “that there is a preferred order of adjectives in Polish AAN phrases, which, however, can be overridden by stylistic reasons” thus, her study is unrelated to the empirical paradigm.

  32. 32.

    In many statistical models, cf. Skousen’s (1989) analogical modeling, after the system has reached a certain level of preference of a given type, self-organization takes place. Speakers are predicted not to chose between options at random any more, but to select one of them. Such regularizations have been long described in language –e.g. the regularization of past tense in Finnish modeled by Skousen (ibid.).

  33. 33.

    to use the title of Surowiecki’s book.

  34. 34.

    This independence is crucial for the wisdom of the crowd to be efficient.

  35. 35.

    Originally, Zip inferred the power laws in language from the principle of minimal effort. Later on this principle was expressed as the optimalization of the effort involved in information transfer between the speaker and the addressee. It must be acknowledged, however, that the possibility of there being also some other sources of power laws, which would not imply the self-organizational character of language, has also been considered. Yet, these other models, cf, an overview in Kwapień (2010), require making a number of assumptions contradictory to what we know about language.

  36. 36.

    Additionally, the community members are motivated to remember the successful idiolect better due to prestige involved.

References

  • Ajdukiewicz, K. (1935). Die syntaktische Konnexit. In S. McCall (Ed.) Polish logic 19201939 (pp. 207–231). Oxford University Press. (Translated from Studia Philosophica, 1, 1–27).

    Google Scholar 

  • Altmann, G. (1978). Towards a theory of language. Glottometrica, 1, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariel, M. (2008). Pragmatics and grammar. In the series Cambridge textbooks in linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bak, P. (1996). How nature works. The science of self-organized criticality. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bak, P., Tang, C., & Weisenfeld, K. (1988). Self-organized criticality. Physical Review E, 38, 364–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. In J. Barwise, & J. Perry. Cambridge, Mass: Brad-ford/M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, D. (1967). Adjectives in English. Attribution and predication. Lingua, 18, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brickhard, M. H., & Campbell, R. L. (1992a). Some foundational studies concerning language Studies. Journal of Pragmatics, 17, 404–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brickhard, M. H., & Campbell, R. L. (1992b). Clearing the grounds. Journal of Pragmatics, 17, 472–486.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brook, R. (1986). Intelligence without representation. Unpublished research report, Cambridge Mass MIT Artificial Intelligence laboratory, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruza, P. D., Kitto, K., Nelson, D., Cathy, L., & McEvoy, C. (2009). Is there something quantum-like about the human mental lexicon? Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 53, 362–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruza, P. D., & Peter, D. (2010). Quantum memory. Australasian Science, 31(1), 34–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1972). Method, model and matter. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2003). Emergence and convergence. Qualitative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge (Toronto Studies in Philosophy) Toronto: UTP inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2005). Pragmemes (a study with reference to English and Italian) Journal of Pragmatics 37, 1355–1371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2006). On Grice’s circle (a theory-internal problem in linguistic theories of the Gricean type.) Journal of Pragmatics 38, 645–669.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2010). On the social practice of indirect reports (further advances in the theory of pragmemes). Journal of Pragmatics, 42(2), 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2002). Thoughts and utterances. The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structure. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1986). Knowledge of language: its nature, origins, and use. New York: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1993). The seas of language: Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., & Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1997). Rethinking innateness: A connectionist perspective on development (neural networks and connectionist modelling). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (2009). The philosophical baby: What children’s minds tell us about truth, love, and the meaning of life. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (2007). Bayesian network, Bayesian learning and cognitive development. Development Science, 10(3), 281–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grabińska, T. (1993). Teoria, Model, Rzeczywistośc. Wrocław: Wrocławska Oficyna Wydawnicza Politechniki Wrocławskiej.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabińska, T. (1994). Poznanie i modelowanie. Wrocław: Wrocławska Oficyna Wydawnicza Politechniki Wrocławskiej.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grabińska, T. (1998). Od Nauki do metafizyki. Warszawa: PWN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E, & Gray, R. D. (1994). Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. The Journal of Philosophy 91(6), 277–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grzybek, P. (2006). Contributions to the science of text and language. Word length studies and related issues. Netherlands: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haken, H. (2010). Synergetics: Introduction and advanced topics. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haspelmath, M. (2008). Frequency vs. iconicity in explaining grammatical asymmetries. Cognitive Linguistics 19(1), 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haspelmath, M. (2006). Creating economical morphosyntactic patterns in language change. In J. Good (Ed.) Language universals and language change. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heylighen, F. (2008). Complexity and self-organization. In M. J. Bates, & M. N. Mack (Eds.) Encyclopedia of library and information sciences (Taylor & Francis).

    Google Scholar 

  • Horst, JS., McMurray, B., & Samuelson, L. K. (2006). Online processing is essential for learning: Understanding fast mapping and word learning in a dynamic connectionist architecture. The Poceedings of the 28th Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1988). Replication and interactors in his Science and Selection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt, K. (2005). Default semantics: Foundations of a compositional theory of acts of communication. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1995). Beyond modularity: A developmental perspective on cognitive science. Cambrigde: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karmiloff, K., & Karmiloff-Smith, A. (2010). Getting to know your baby. London: Carroll & Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. (2007). Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, R. (1994). On language change: The invisible hand in language. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I. (2010). The paradox of communication: socio-cognitive approach to Pragmatics. Pragmatics and Society, 1(1), 55–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirby, S. (1999) . Syntax out of Learning: The cultural evolution of structured communication in a population of induction algorithms. In D. Floreano, J. D. Nicond, & F. Mondado (Eds.), ECAL99, 694--703.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koehler, R. Synergetic Linguistics. In R. Koehler, G. Altmann, Rajmund G. Piotrowski (Eds.), Quantitative Linguistik- Quantitative Linquistics. Ein internationales Handbuch, Berlin/New York: de Gruyter, 760--774.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kopytko, R. (2001a). From Cartesian toward non-Cartesian pragmatics. Journal of Pragmatics, 6, 783–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kopytko, R. (2001b). The great dissolution a la Michel Foucault and the non-Cartesian pragmatics. Journal of Pragmatics, 10, 1637–1642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kopytko, R. (2004). The affective context in non-Cartesian pragmatics: A theoretical grounding. Journal of Pragmatics, 3, 521–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kopytko, R. (1998). Relational pragmatics: Towards a holistic view of pragmatic Phenomena. Studia Anglica Posnaniensia, 33, 195–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kopytko, R. (1995). Against rationalistic pragmatics. Journal of Pragmatics, 23, 475–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kwapień, J. (2010). Fizyczne charakterystyki złożoności. The Institute of Nuclear Physics of Polish Academy of Science in Kraków. Raport 2036/AP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (2000). Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lin, L., Osan, R., Shoham, S., Jin, W., Zuo, W., & Tsien, J. Z. (2005). Identification of network level coding units for real time representation of episodic experiences in the hippocampus. In Proceedings of the National Academy of Science USA, 102 no 17, pp. 6125–6130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lin, L., Osan, R., & Tsien, J. Z. (2006). Organizing principles of real-time memory encoding neural cliques assemblies and universal neural codes. Trends in Neurosciences, 29(1), 48–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lin, L., Chen, G., Kuang, H., Wang, D., & Tsien, J. Z. (2007). Neural encoding and the concept of nest in the mouse brain. In Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, USA, 104 no 14, pp. 6066–6071.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1987). Woman fire and dangerous things. Chicago: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. W. (1987). Foundations of cognitive grammar. Stanford: SUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luther, P., & Fenk, A. (1984). Wird der Wortlaut von Saetzen zwangslaeufig schneller vergessen als ihr Inhalt? Zeitschrift fuer Experimentelle und Angewandte Psychologie, 31(1), 101--123

    Google Scholar 

  • Mey, J. L. (2001). Pragmatics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mey, J. L., & Haberland, H. (2002). Linguistics and pragmatics, 25 years after. Journal of Pragmatics, 34(12), 1671–1682.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mey, J. L. (2010). Reference and pragmeme. Journal of Pragmatics, 42, 2882–2888.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mey, J. L. Forthcoming. Modular, cellular, integral: A pragmatic elephant? In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, & M. Carapezza (Eds.) Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mountcastle, V. (1998). Perceptual neuroscience; the cerebral cortex. Cambridge: Harvard UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1960). Minds and machines. In S. Hook (Ed.) Dimensions of mind (pp. 148–180). New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of meaning. In K. Gunderson (Ed.) Language, mind, and knowledge Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1988). Representation and reality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2011). Truth-conditional pragmatics. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searl, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sachs, J. S. (1967). Recognition memory for syntactic and semantic aspects of connected discourse. Percept Psychophys. 2:437--442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seymour, M. (2010). Speech act pluralism, minimal content, and pragmemes. Journal of pragmatics, 42(11), 2870–2881.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skausan, R. (1989). Analogical modelling of language. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (2010). Philosophy of language. In L. Cummings (Ed.), The pragmatics encyclopedia (pp. 348–353). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (2005). In defense of non-sentential assertion. In Z. Szabó (Ed.) Semantics vs. pragmatics (pp. 383–457). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (2006a). Words and thoughts: Subsentences, ellipsis, and the philosophy of language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. J. (2006b). Neither fragments nor ellipsis. In L. Progovac et al. (Eds.) The syntax of nonsententials. (pp. 93–116). Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2007). Language in context. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sweetser, E. E. (1990). From etymology to pragmatics. Metaphorical and cultural aspects of semantic structure. Cambridge: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (2001). Unshadowed thought: Representation in thought and language. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka, A. (1972). Semantic primitives. Linguistische Forschungen no 23. Frankfurt: Athenaeum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka, A. (1985). Lexicography and conceptual analysis. Ann Arbor: Karoma.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka, A. (2010). Bilingualism and cognition: The perspective from semantics. In V. Cook, & B. Bassetti (Eds.) Language and bilingual cognition New York, NY: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Włodarczyk, A. (2011). Distributed grammar. www.celta.paris-sorbonne.fr/anasem/intexASMIC.html.

  • Wulf, S. (2003). A multifactorial corpus analysis of adjective order in English. International Journal of Corpus Linguistics, 8(2), 245–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1963). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Originally 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1961). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Originally 1921.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (1997). A note on the extended functional analysis. Journal of Pragmatics, 27, 841–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (1999). The selective mode of language use; the way nature language adopted itself to describing the word around us. Zeszyty Naukowe UJ, 119, 173–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (2007). The selective mode of language use and the quantized communicative field. Journal of Pragmatics 39(5), 813–830.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D, (2007b), Proceduralny model języka. Językoznawstwo z pozycji teorii modeli nauk empirycznych. WUJ. Kraków.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziff, P. (1960). Semantic Analysis. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zipf, G. K. (1949). Human behavior and the principle of least effort. Boston: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zipf, G. K. (1935). The psycho-biology of language. London: Routledge & Sons Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dorota Zielińska .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zielińska, D. (2013). The Mechanism of the Form-Content Correlation Process in the Paradigm of Socio-Natural Sciences. In: Capone, A., Lo Piparo, F., Carapezza, M. (eds) Perspectives on Linguistic Pragmatics. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01014-4_19

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics