Skip to main content

Writing Letters in the Age of Grice

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 1))

Abstract

This article aims to investigate the notion of implicature and its connections with speaker’s intentions, communicative responsibility and normativity. Some scholars stress the normative character of conversational implicatures more than their psychological dimension. In a normative perspective, conversational implicatures don’t correspond to what the speaker intends to implicate, but should be interpreted as enriching or correcting inferences licensed by the text. My chapter aims to show that the idea of an implicature that the speaker does not intend to convey is not persuasive. In Grice’s theory conversational implicatures are speaker-meant: this means that inferences derived by the addressee but not intended by the speaker should not count as conversational implicatures. On the contrary, I will claim that propositions intended by the speaker and not recognised by the addressee should count as implicatures, if the speaker has made her communicative intention available to her audience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Grice (1975, 1989, p. 34).

  2. 2.

    Cf. Grice (1989).

  3. 3.

    Grice (1975, 1989, p. 24).

  4. 4.

    Grice (1967, 1989, p. 118).

  5. 5.

    According to Grice, what is said (i.e. B.) is "closely related to the conventional meaning of the… sentence… uttered" (i.e. A.) and must correspond to "the elements of the [sentence], their order, and their syntactic character". It is closely related but not identical to what the sentence means, because the sentence may contain ambiguities or indexicals: Grice (1969, 1989, p. 87).

  6. 6.

    Grice (1975, 1989, p. 26): "Our talk exchanges do not normally consist of a succession of disconnected remarks, and would not be rational if they did. They are characteristically, to some degree at least, cooperative efforts; and each participant recognizes in them, to some extent, a common purpose or set of purposes, or at least a mutually accepted direction".

  7. 7.

    Grice (1975, 1989, p. 26): "Make your conversational contribution such as is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you are engaged".

  8. 8.

    Cf. Grice (1975, 1989, pp. 26–27).

  9. 9.

    Grice (1975, 1989, pp. 30–31).

  10. 10.

    In my chapter I will focus on the normative/psychological debate and will not address many interesting points raised by Grice's definition; in particular I will not deal with the distinction between "saying" and "making as if to say". On this and related points, see Bianchi (2009) and (2013).

  11. 11.

    According to Saul "only if": Saul (2002a, p. 231). For a different point of view, see Neale (1992, pp. 527–529).

  12. 12.

    Grice (1975, 1989, p. 33).

  13. 13.

    Grice (1975, 1989, p. 33).

  14. 14.

    Saul (2002a, p. 229).

  15. 15.

    Cf. Saul (2002a, p. 229).

  16. 16.

    The five cases are taken, with variations, from Saul (2002a).

  17. 17.

    Cf. Saul (2002a, p. 231): "The implicature was blocked because a speaker cannot conversationally implicate something which the audience is not required to assume that she thinks". In this example, as in other examples, there is a crucial distinction to be made: the one between the intended addressee (the addressee intended by the speaker) and the actual audience. In order to adhere to Saul's arguments I will not make use of the distinction in what follows.

  18. 18.

    Saul (2002a, p. 242).

  19. 19.

    Cf. Bach and Harnish (1979, p. 15): "its fulfilment consists in its recognition". Bach and Harnish's theory is a development of Grice's, and of his intention-based and inferential view of communication. To many, however, their position is too strong.

  20. 20.

    Cf. Green (2002, 2007), Saul (2002a, b) and Sbisà (2007).

  21. 21.

    Cf. Saul (2002a, p. 244): "There are, then, cases in which we can reasonably say that the audience should have worked out the conversational implicature, even if they failed to do so"; Sbisà (2007, pp. 122, 126 and 192).

  22. 22.

    According to Marina Sbisà, a conversational implicature isn't necessarily a proposition believed by the speaker, but a proposition that should be accepted by the speaker. This means that the speaker may be wrong about an implicature: even if she does not intend to convey a particular implicature, there are cases in which this should in any case be worked out by the addressee. In Sbisà's framework, implicatures are normative virtual objects. The alleged implicature does not count as conveyed meaning only if to attribute that communicative intention to the speaker would be absurd or contradictory: but if the text licenses it, the derivation of a particular implicature will be legitimate, even if S has no intention of conveying it.

  23. 23.

    Grice (1975, 1989, p. 34).

  24. 24.

    Cf. Davis (2007, Sect. 2): "conditions [(a)–(c)] say nothing about what S intends". For a different opinion, see Neale (1992, p. 528).

  25. 25.

    Grice (1975, 1989, p. 31). Cf. Davis (2007, Sect. 2): "Grice does mention intention at the appropriate place when he is setting out the ‘Calculability Assumption' of his theory".

  26. 26.

    Grice (1961, 1965 p. 448).

  27. 27.

    Grice (1961, 1989, p. 229).

  28. 28.

    Cf. Saul (2002a, pp. 238–239).

  29. 29.

    Davis (1998, 2007).

  30. 30.

    Roberts (1997, p. 196). Cf. Donnellan (1968).

  31. 31.

    Saul (2002a, p. 245): "conversationally implicating something… fails to guarantee audience uptake but does mean that the speaker has fulfilled her communicative responsibilities with regard to what she wants to communicate… she may not have communicated her intended message, but she has made it available".

  32. 32.

    Cf. Predelli (2002, pp. 315–316).

  33. 33.

    Cf. Davis (2010).

References

  • Bach, Kent, and Robert M. Harnish. 1979. Linguistic communication and speech acts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, Claudia. 2009. Pragmatica cognitiva. I meccanismi della comunicazione. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, Claudia. 2013. Implicating. In Pragmatics of speech actions, eds. M. Sbisà, and K. Turner. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter: 83–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Wayne. 1998. Implicature: Intention, convention, and principle in the failure of Gricean theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Wayne. 2007. How normative is implicature? Journal of Pragmatics 39: 1655–1672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, Wayne. 2010. Implicature. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, (Winter 2010 Ed.), forthcoming http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/implicature/.

  • Donnellan, Keith. 1968. Putting humpty dumpty together again. The Philosophical Review 77: 203–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, Mitchell. 2002. Review of Implicature: Intention, convention, and principle in the failure of Gricean theory, by Wayne Davis. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65: 241–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, Mitchell. 2007. Self-expression. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Herbert Paul. 1961. The causal theory of perception. The Aristotelian Society: Proceedings, Supplementary Volume, 35, 121–52, reprinted in R. Swartz ed. Perceiving, Sensing and Knowing, Garden City, N. Y., Doubleday, Anchor, 1965, reprinted in Grice 1989, 224–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Herbert Paul. 1967. Logic and conversation. In Syntax and semantics 3: Speech Acts, 41-58, eds. Cole, P. and Morgan, J., 1–143. New York: Academic Press, reprinted in Grice 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Herbert Paul. 1969. Utterer’s meaning and intentions. Philosophical Review 68: 147–177, reprinted in Grice 1989, 86–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Herbert Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation (1967). In Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts, eds. Cole, P. and Morgan, J., 41–58. New York: Academic Press, reprinted in Grice 1989, 22–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Herbert Paul. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neale, Stephen. 1992. Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguistics and Philosophy 15: 509–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, Stefano. 2002. Intentions, indexicals and communication. Analysis 62(4): 310–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, Lawrence D. 1997. How demonstrations connect with referential intentions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75(2): 190–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. 2001. Wayne A. Davis, Implicature: Intention, convention, and principle in the failure of Gricean theory. Nous 35: 631–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. 2002a. Speaker meaning, what is said, and what is implicated. Nous 36: 228–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, Jennifer. 2002b. What is said and psychological reality: Grice’s project and relevance theorists’ criticisms. Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 347–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sbisà, Marina. 2007. Detto, non detto. Le forme della comunicazione implicita. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudia Bianchi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bianchi, C. (2013). Writing Letters in the Age of Grice. In: Capone, A., Lo Piparo, F., Carapezza, M. (eds) Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01011-3_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics