Skip to main content

Debating with Myself: Towards the Psycho-Pragmatics and Onto-Pragmatics of the Dialectical Self

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 1))

  • 1514 Accesses

Abstract

The above experiences were indeed experienced by me while writing this piece. Yet, none of them is idiosyncratic to Marcelo Dascal. Anyone who has engaged in writing has certainly experienced them, albeit perhaps without acknowledging and naming them as I suggested above. Nor are these phenomena typical of this particular kind of intellectual activity.

We all struggle against each other. And there is always something in us which struggles against something else in us [Quoted in P. Dews, “The nouvelle philosophie and Foucault”. Economy and Society 8: 164–165 (1979)].

Michel Foucault.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I wish to thank Varda Dascal, Yaron Senderowicz, Ilana Arbel, Adelino Cardoso, and Mark Glouberman for their suggestions and especially for being the ‘others’ in a debate that helped me in conducting the self-debate that this essay reflects.

  2. 2.

    Nicole (1999: 310, 311).

  3. 3.

    Paragraph 82 of the Brunschvicg edition, as published in Pascal (1960).

  4. 4.

    Recall, for example, his experiments on the vacuum and his essay De l'esprit géometrique. Pascal (1985) contains, along with this essay, the draft of a Preface for a planned Traité du vide, as well as other posthumously published texts, notably the Ecrits sur la Grâce—a judicious juxtaposition of writings, which highlights the dual role Pascal assigns to the imagination.

  5. 5.

    Quoted in Piro (1999: 168).

  6. 6.

    In my previous work on inter-personal debates (e.g., Dascal 1998, 2000), I have employed the expression ‘polemical exchange’ as the general term for their various types. In the present context, I prefer the more neutral term ‘debate’.

  7. 7.

    Leibniz (1903: 355). He also employs the terms conjunctio for the former and convenientia for the latter. On this classification of relations and their counterparts in 19th–20th century thought, see Dascal (1978: 106–115).

  8. 8.

    For the distinction between socio- and psycho-pragmatics, see Dascal (1983: 42–52). Viewing ‘psycho-pragmatics’ as a branch of pragmatics or the theory of language use is justified in the present case insofar as one takes into account that language is actually ‘used’ in mental processes not only by way of employing in them words or a 'mental lexicon' (Aitchinson 1994), but also through the presence in such processes of underlying structures that are originally or typically linguistic. One such structure is the dialectic structure of inter-personal debate (cf. Dascal 2002).

  9. 9.

    Proust (1954: 562).

  10. 10.

    John Horne Tooke, Diversions of Purley (1786), II, 51b (quoted in Aarsleff 1967: 13).

  11. 11.

    For further analysis of the metaphoric and metonymic relations in ARGUMENT IS WAR, see Dascal (2004a, b).

  12. 12.

    Hampshire, who elaborates the Aristotelian notion of deliberation as the cornerstone of his moral theory, puts to use the external-internal debate analogy in this vivid passage: "The picture of the mind that gives substance to the notion of practical reason is a picture of a council chamber, in which the agent's contrary interests are represented around the table, each speaking for itself. The chairman, who represents the will, weighs the arguments and the intensity of the feeling conveyed by the arguments, and then issues an order to be acted on. The order is a decision and an intention, to be followed by its execution. This policy is the outcome of the debate in the council chamber" (Hampshire 1991: 51).

  13. 13.

    Aristotle considered the notion of deliberation sufficiently important on its own to write a special treatise devoted to it (Peri Symboulías, which is listed in Diogenes Laertius’ catalogue). On possible traces of this treatise in the Rhetoric, see the Spanish translation and commentary by Q. Racionero, pp. 99, 214, 222.

  14. 14.

    In this paragraph, I refer to, paraphrase and extrapolate statements that can be found in Rhet. 1357a–b, 1358b, 1359a; Nic. Eth. 1112a–1113a, 1139a–b, 1141a, 1142b.

  15. 15.

    For details, see Dascal (2005).

  16. 16.

    “Rationes non esse numerandas sed ponderandas” (reasons are not to be counted but weighed), stresses Leibniz on several occasions (this quote, e.g., is from his letter to Gabriel Wagner, 27.2.1697; in Leibniz 1875, vol. 7: 521).

  17. 17.

    Again, a phrase often employed by Leibniz. The locus classicus is the Discours de Metaphysique [1686], par. 13 (in Leibniz 1999: 1546).

  18. 18.

    It should be noted that, being based upon non-conclusive inferences, soft rationality provides only a weak warrant for its recommendations, if compared with the strong warrant provided by hard rationality. Nevertheless, this does not mean that it is chronically guilty of a cognitive error analogous to weakness of will, which Davidson calls ‘weakness of the warrant’ and defines as follows: “a person has evidence both for and against a hypothesis; the person judges that relative to all the evidence available to him, the hypothesis is more probable than not; yet he does not accept the hypothesis” (Davidson 1986: 81). A person using soft rationality may, of course, incur in this error, but only if he fails to take into account the reasons he considers relevant, to assign them proper weights, to compare them properly, and to admit that the result may be overridden by the eventual presentation of ‘heavier’ reasons.

  19. 19.

    Although certainly relevant for the soft vs. hard rationality distinction, Hampshire's (1991: 52) emphasis on the argument-dependence of a deliberative decision (as opposed to the argument-independence of the rightness or wrongness of an arithmetical calculation) focuses on the fact that a moral or political decision is a decision to act for certain reasons, and not on the soft character of the inference, which is what I am stressing here.

  20. 20.

    In the same vein, Leibniz writes: “The nature of the will requires freedom, which consists in that a voluntary action is spontaneous and deliberate, i.e., that it excludes necessity, which suppresses deliberation” (Causa Dei [1710], in Leibniz 1875–1890, vol. 6: 441).

  21. 21.

    “[A]s a result of deliberation we form an intention. But when the moment comes there is an indefinite range of choices open to us and several of those choices are attractive or motivated on other grounds. For many of the actions we do for a reason, there are conflicting reasons for doing not that action but something else. Sometimes we act on those reasons and not on our original intention. The solution to the problem of akrasia is as simple as that” (Searle 2005: 76–77).

  22. 22.

    This might explain Hampshire's notion of argument-dependence of a deliberative decision (see note 20), while at the same time not restricting it to the case in which the decision is that of acting for certain reasons.

  23. 23.

    From the choice for the jacket of Rationality in Action of Vermeer’s masterpiece Woman Holding a Balance, which depicts a situation of extremely delicate weighing of jewels, to the explicit use of the balance model—the emblem of soft rationality—there would be but a small step, were it not for the gap.

  24. 24.

    Letter from Burnett to Leibniz, 3 May 1697 (in Leibniz 1875, vol. 3: 198).

  25. 25.

    “This is how the Areopagytes would in effect absolve this man whose case was too difficult to be decided; they would postpone it for a long time and grant themselves one hundred years to reflect about it” (Leibniz, Nouveaux essais sur l’entendement humain [1705], 2.21.23; in Leibniz 1875, vol. 5: 167).

  26. 26.

    “The fixation of belief”. In Peirce (1931–1958, vol. 5: 235; first published in Popular Science Monthly 12: 1–15, 1877). For a critical discussion of this article by Peirce, see Dascal and Dascal (2004).

  27. 27.

    The quotes in this paragraph are from Nic. Eth. 1151b4-15.

  28. 28.

    On the distinction between ‘reasons’ and ‘causes’, see Davidson (1963).

  29. 29.

    Furthermore, the across boundary possibility of causal interaction may be all that is required for the intervention, in a self-dispute, of an ‘external’ factor not directly involved in it, which can however, be causally effective in ‘dissolving’ it or reducing its level of conflict. Consider some sort of self-regulating mechanism analogous to an analyst who interprets the fighting parties’ aims and moves in the hope of dissolving or reducing the unrest or the dysfunctions caused by the conflict, or the inner analogue of Kant’s ‘umpire’ or ‘legislator’ (similar to Smith’s ‘impartial observer in the breast’), who does not take sides in the metaphysical disputes between ‘dogmatic sects’ but only draws from their combats lessons about the limits of pure reason (Kant 1971: Aviii, A423, B452; Dascal 2000, for further details). These speculations suggests that the quarreling parts of the ‘self’ share, after all, a common interest in preserving a functioning condition, a well being that regulates the wildness of self-disputes.

References

  • Ainslie, George. 1982. A behavioral economic approach to the defense mechanisms: Freud’s energy theory revisited. Social Science Information 21(6): 735–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ainslie, George. 1986. Beyond microeconomics. Conflict among interests in a multiple self as a determinant of value. In ed. Elster, 133–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aitchinson, Jean. 1994. Words in the mind: An introduction to the mental lexicon, 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aarsleff, Hans. 1967. The study of language in England, 1780–1860. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1996. Nicomachean Ethics, (trans: Rackham, H., introd. S. Watt. Ware). Hertfordshire: Wordsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1990. Retórica, (trans: introd. and notes by Q. Racionero). Madrid: Gredos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, Mikhail.M. 1984. Problems of Dostoevsky’s Poetics. ed. Emerson, C. 1984. (trans: Emerson, C.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brehm, Jack W. 1956. Post-decision changes in the desirability of alternatives. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 52: 384–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 1978. La sémiologie de Leibniz. Paris: Aubier-Montaigne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 1983. Pragmatics and the philosophy of mind, vol. 1. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 1992. Why does language matter to artificial intelligence? Minds and Machines 2(2): 145–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 1995. The dispute on the primacy of thinking or speaking. In Philosophy of languageAn international handbook of contemporary research, vol. 2, eds. Dascal, M., D. Gerhardus, K. Lorenz, and G. Meggle, 1024–1041. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 1998. Types of polemics and types of polemical moves. In Dialogue analysis VI (= Proceedings of the 6th IADA conference, Prague 1996), vol. 1, eds. Čmejrková, S., J. Hoffmannová, O. Müllerová, and J. Světlá, 15–33. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 2000. Controversies and epistemology. In Philosophy of science (=Vol. 10 of proceedings of the twentieth world congress of philosophy), ed. Tian Yu Cao. 159–192. Philadelphia: Philosophers Index Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 2002. Language as a cognitive technology. International Journal of Cognition and Technology 1: 35–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 2003. Interpretation and understanding. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 2004. Argument, war and the role of the media in conflict management. In Jews, muslims and mass media, ed. Parfitt, T. with Y. Egorova. 228–248. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo. 2005. The balance of reason. In Logic, thought and action, ed. D. Vanderveken, 27–47. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, Marcelo, and Dascal, Varda. 2004. A des-fixação da crença. In O Processo da Crença, eds. Gil, F., P. Livet, and J.P. Cabral. 321–353. Lisboa: Gradiva.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1963. Actions, reasons, and causes. In Davidson, D. 2001. 3–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1969. How weakness of the will is possible?. In Davidson, D. 2001. 21–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1986. Deception and division. In ed. Elster, J. 79–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 2001. Essays on actions and events, 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon. 1986a. Introduction. In ed. Elster, J. 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon (ed.). 1986b. The multiple self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Festinger, Leon. 1957. A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Festinger, Leon (ed.). 1964. Conflict, decision, and dissonance. London: Tavistock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampshire, Stuart. 1991. Innocence and experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson, Roman. 1962. Deux aspects du langage et deux types d'aphasie. Les Temps Modernes 188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakobson, Roman. 1964. Deux aspects du langage et deux types d’aphasie. In Essais de Lingüistique Générale, ed. R. Jakobson, 43–67. Paris: Minuit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1971. Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Leipzig: Reclam (A = 1st ed., 1781; B = 2nd ed., 1787).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried W. 1875–1890. Die Philosophischen Schriften, ed. Gerhardt, C.J. Berlin [repr. Hildesheim, Georg Olms, 1965].

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried W. 1903. Opuscules et fragments inédits de Leibniz, ed. Couturat, L. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried W. 1999. Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, series 6, vol. 4, ed. Leibniz-Forschungstelle der Universität Münster. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1690. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. ed. Yolton, J.W. London and New York: Everyman’s Library (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicole, Pierre. 1999. De la connaissance de soi-même. In Essais de morale, ed. Thirouin, L. 309–379. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France (1st ed. 1675).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, Blaise. 1960. Pensées. Text of the Brunschvicg edition, with introduction and notes by Ch.-M. des Granges. Paris: Garnier Frères [1st, posthumous ed. 1669].

    Google Scholar 

  • Pascal, Blaise. 1985. De l’esprit géométrique, Ecrits sur la Grâce et autres textes, ed. Clair, A. Paris: Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pears, David. 1986. The goals and strategies of self-deception. In ed. Elster, J. 59–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Charles S. 1931–1958. Collected papers of charles sanders peirce, ed. Hartshorne, C. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piro, Francesco. 1999. Il Retore Interno: Immaginazione e passione all’alba dell’età moderna. Napoli: La Città del Sole.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proust, Marcel. 1954. A l’ombre des jeunes filles en fleurs, 1ère partie. In M. Proust, A la recherché du temps perdu, vol. 1, ed. Clarac, P. and A. Ferré. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Amelie O. 1986. Self-deception, akrasia and irrationality. In ed. Elster 115–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 1983. Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 2001. Rationality in action. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 2005. Desire, deliberation and action. In Logic, thought and action, ed. D. Vanderveken, 49–78. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Senault, Jean F. 1664. De l’usage des passions. Paris: Le Petit [1st ed. 1641].

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Adam. 1976. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. Raphael, D.D. and A.L. Macfie. Oxford: Clarendon Press [6th ed. 1790].

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Barbara H. 1997. Belief and resistance: Dynamics of contemporary intellectual controversy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thibodeau, Ruth, and Elliot Aronson. 1992. Taking a closer look: Reasserting the role of the self-concept in dissonance theory. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 18: 591–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, Lev S. 1962. Thought and language (trans. Hanfmann, E. and G. Vakar). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, John B. 1913. Psychology as the behaviorist views it. The Psychological Review 20: 158–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marcelo Dascal .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dascal, M. (2013). Debating with Myself: Towards the Psycho-Pragmatics and Onto-Pragmatics of the Dialectical Self. In: Capone, A., Lo Piparo, F., Carapezza, M. (eds) Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01011-3_26

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics