Skip to main content

Squaring the Circle

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 1))

Abstract

Making the distinction between semantics and pragmatics has proven to be a tricky task, leading to several problems that look like Gordian knots, or worse; perhaps semantics and pragmatics are so tangled that separating them is impossible, like squaring the circle. A widespread, plausible, Grice-inspired view of the distinction is threatened by what (Levinson Presumptive meanings. MIT Press/Bradford Books, Cambridge, Mass, 2000) called ‘Grice’s circle.’ Gricean inferences to derive the pragmatic content of the utterance (such as conversational implicatures) require the determination of what is said (also known as the ‘semantic content’ or the ‘literal truth-conditions’); but determining what is said (by processes of disambiguation, precisification, reference fixing, etc.) requires pragmatic inference. In a nutshell, pragmatic inference both requires and is required by the determination of what is said. Thus, there is no way to unravel semantics and pragmatics. In this paper, we will show how to square Grice’s circle. We untie the semantics/pragmatics knot, without using any of Alexander’s methods: slicing it with a sword or removing the (semantic) pin around which it was bound. The approach consists in assuming a minimal but truth-conditionally complete notion of semantic content (Perry Reference and reflexivity. CSLI Publications, Stanford, 2001), which doesn’t constitute what is said by the utterance, but does provide the required input for pragmatic reasoning.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The category of conventional implicatures doesn’t fit this picture, however, since being the result of the semantics (of certain words) of the sentence uttered, they do not contribute, according to Grice, to what is said.

  2. 2.

    For a recent defense of Gazdar’s view on the semantics/pragmatics divide that attempts to avoid Grice’s circle, see Capone (2006).

  3. 3.

    According to Bach (2011), Levinson makes a mistake to the extent that he sees Grice himself as having the views that lead to the circle. According to Bach, Levinson conflates two senses of ‘determine’: one related to what the grammar delivers in combination with context, the other with the psychological process of ascertaining the content by a hearer:

    “He [Grice] never claimed that the hearer’s inference proceeds from first identifying what the speaker says to then considering whether there is any ostensible breach of the maxims and, if so and assuming the speaker is being cooperative and is aiming to communicate something, to seek a plausible candidate for what that could be.”

    This is doubtless a correct point about Grice, and shows that the circle need not be temporal. But it does not explain how Gricean considerations are brought to bear prior to identifying what is said; this is what we try to do.

  4. 4.

    See Recanati (2010).

  5. 5.

    Grice included in his overall picture of meaning and communication non-linguistic ‘utterances’ like gestures and movements, but we will limit the discussion to linguistic utterances.

  6. 6.

    These more technical terms used by philosophers are not without problems, since they can suggest that implicatures are not contents of the utterance, or they are not propositional. Gricean implicatures (at least conversational particularized ones) are also full-blown truth-conditional (though more or less indeterminate) contents of the utterance, but we ignore this issue here, and follow common practice using ‘content’ only to talk about the contents that are on the ‘what-is-said’ part of the Gricean divide.

  7. 7.

    In American English this is an example of two words, ‘vice’ and ‘vise,’ both pronounced/vais/. Parallel considerations would apply. But we follow British English, and Grice, in taking it to be ambiguity.

  8. 8.

    See (Korta and Perry 2006a, 2008 and 2011). In the latter we distinguish utterance-bound, speaker-bound, network-bound, referential and designational contents. We contend that any of those can be and is the right ‘input’ for the inference of implicatures.

  9. 9.

    Or, more precisely, the speaker-bound truth-conditions. See Korta and Perry (2011, 2013).

References

  • Bach, Kent. 1994. Conversational impliciture. Mind and Language 9: 124–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, Kent. 2011. Review of truth-conditional pragmatics (François Recanati). Notre Dame philosophical reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/25657-truth-conditional-pragmatics-2/. Accessed 26 Sept 2011.

  • Borg, Emma. 2004. Minimalist semantics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, Alessandro. 2006. On Grice’s circle (a theory-internal problem in linguistic theories of the Gricean type). Journal of Pragmatics 38: 645–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, Herman, and Ernie Lepore. 2005. Insensitive semantics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, Robyn. 2002. Thoughts and utterances. The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, Gerald. 1979. Pragmatics: Implicature, presupposition, and logical form. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. Paul. 1967. Logic and conversation. In The logic of grammar, eds. D. Davidson and G. Harman, 1975, 64–75. Encino: Dickenson. Also published in Syntax and Semantics 3: Speech Acts, eds. P. Cole and J.L. Morgan, 1975, 41–58. New York: Academic Press. Reprinted in Grice 1989: 22–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. Paul. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, David. 1989. Demonstratives. In Themes from Kaplan, eds. J. Almog, J. Perry and H. Wettstein. New York: Oxford University Press, 561–614.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korta, Kepa, and John Perry. 2006a. Three demonstrations and a funeral. Mind and Language 21: 166–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korta, Kepa and John Perry. 2006b. Pragmatics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Revised March 2011), ed. Zalta, Edward, N. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatics/.

  • Korta, Kepa, and John Perry. 2008. The pragmatic circle. Synthese 165: 347–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korta, Kepa, and John Perry. 2011. Critical pragmatics. An inquiry into reference and communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korta, Kepa, and John Perry. 2013. Highlights of critical pragmatics: reference and the contents of the utterance. Intercultural Pragmatics 10(1): 161–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, Stephen. 2000. Presumptive meanings. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, John. 1986. Thought without representation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary volume), 60: 137–51. Reprinted in Perry 2000: 171–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, John. 2000. The problem of the essential indexical and other essays expanded. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, John. 2001. Reference and reflexivity. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, François. 2010. Truth-conditional pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The first author is grateful to his colleagues of the group ‘Language, Action and Thought’ at the Institute for Logic, Cognition, Language and Information (ILCLI) for their comments and criticisms, especially to Eros Corazza, Joana Garmendia, María Ponte and Larraitz Zubeldia. This work was partially supported by a grant of the Basque Government (IT323-10 and IT780-13) and the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation (FFI2009-08574 and FF12012-37726).

The second author appreciates the support of the philosophy department at the University of California, Riverside, the Center for the Study of Language and Information at Stanford University, and conversations with many colleagues and students.

Both authors want to thank Alessandro Capone for his infinite enthusiasm and patience.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kepa Korta .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Korta, K., Perry, J. (2013). Squaring the Circle. In: Capone, A., Lo Piparo, F., Carapezza, M. (eds) Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-01011-3_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics