Skip to main content

Consolidation of Axiomatic Set Theory

  • Chapter
Labyrinth of Thought

Part of the book series: Science Networks. Historical Studies ((SNHS,volume 23))

  • 332 Accesses

Abstract

After 1918, most important contributions to the foundations of abstract set theory relied on modem axiom systems. But until the 1920s few authors adopted Zermelo’s axiom system explicitly.2 As we saw in the preceding chapter, many favored the theory of types because it seemed to offer a safer framework, and at the same time it was sufficient for the limited amount of set theory that is necessary in so-called classical mathematics. As late as 1939 Alonzo Church was writing that the simplified theory of types and Zermelo’s set theory were essentially similar, and the “safest cities of refuge” for classicist mathematicians at the time.3 But the Zermelo system had to compete with another alternative, the system of von Neumann, presented in 1925 and developed later by Bernays and Gödel (see §3).

We shall carefully investigate those ways of forming notions and those modes of inference that are fruitful; we shall nurse them, support them, and make them usable, whenever there is the slightest promise of success. No one shall be able to drive us from the paradise that Cantor created for us.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. [Hilbert 1926] as translated in [van Heijenoort 1967, 375–76].

    Google Scholar 

  2. Among the few examples are Hessenberg [1909] and Hartogs [1915]. The latter proved that, in Zermelo’s system without AC, the comparability of cardinals implies Well-Ordering.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See [Church 1937, 95; 1939, 69–70].

    Google Scholar 

  4. Sierpinski was interested in open problems, like those related to AC and CH, their consequences and equivalences. See [Moore 1982; 1989].

    Google Scholar 

  5. The first to argue in earnest for Replacement, and to work out its consequences, was von Neumann in 1923. The history of Replacement has been carefully studied by Hallett [1984].

    Google Scholar 

  6. Fraenkel, who was a zionist, moved to Palestina and became a professor at the Hebrew University in Jerusalem in 1929. See his autobiography [Fraenkel 1967].

    Google Scholar 

  7. The most important instance was Separation, apart from which only the axiom of Elementary Sets was reduced to postulating pairs {a,b} (whence the name in use today, Axiom of Pairs).

    Google Scholar 

  8. But, unlike von Neumann, he could not see whether this detoured way of dealing with ordinals “presents real advantages,” although it throws new light on Cantor’s theory [1917a, 217]. Mirimanoff [1917, 45] considered also a criterion of set existence that would be characteristic of von Neumann’s axiomatization of set theory.

    Google Scholar 

  9. [Mirimanoff 1917, 38]: “Quelles sont les conditions nécessaires et suffisantes pour qu’un ensemble d’individus existe?”

    Google Scholar 

  10. See [Mirimanoff 1919, 35]. In this later paper his lack of understanding for axiomatic issues comes out clearly.

    Google Scholar 

  11. This point was emphasized by Hallett [1984].

    Google Scholar 

  12. This had become clear to him in correspondence with Fraenkel himself [1928, 323].

    Google Scholar 

  13. [von Neumann 1928, 334]. I have introduced a slight change to simplify the original notation.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Zermelo did not spell out the details of his logical standpoint, particularly the effect of second-order logic for the Skolem paradox. But see [Zermelo 1931] and [Grattan-Guinness 1979; Moore 1980; Dawson 1985a]. A clear discussion of the logical aspects can be found in [Shapiro 1991] or [Lavine 1994].

    Google Scholar 

  15. [Zermelo 1930, 31]: “Axiom der Fundierung: Jede (rückschreitende) Kette von Elementen, in welcher jedes Glied Element des vorangehenden ist, bricht mit endlichem Index ab bei einem Urelement. Oder, was gleichbedeutend ist: Jeder Teilbereich T enthält wenigstens ein Element t o , das kein Element t in That.“

    Google Scholar 

  16. Today one would require (with first-order quantification) that every non-empty set s in the domain have at least one element t, such that no element oft is also an element of s.

    Google Scholar 

  17. The `layers’ Q a of Zermelo are not cumulative, in contrast to his `sections’ P a [1930, 36]. Therefore it is the second which correspond to the ranks of the usual cumulative hierarchy; instead of P a we shall write V a for the ranks, as has become customary.

    Google Scholar 

  18. This term is taken from [Hellman 1989] and [Lavine 1994].

    Google Scholar 

  19. The same applies to different models with a single, common `basis’ of urelements (that differ in their `characteristic’). Likewise, of two different models with the same `characteristic,’ one is always isomorphic to a subdomain of the other [1930, 42].

    Google Scholar 

  20. For a careful analysis of this paper, see Hallett’s introduction to his translation of the paper in [Ewald 1996, vol.2].

    Google Scholar 

  21. Indeed, a double sequence of models, since we also have to take into account the many possible `bases’ of urelements [Zermelo 1930, 42, 47].

    Google Scholar 

  22. Gödel had already presented this conception in conferences during the 1930s; see volume 3 of his Collected Works.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Strictly speaking, it is wrong to say that Gödel offered the iterative conception as justification of the ZFC axioms. This was done by later authors. See [Klaua 1964], [Kreisel 1965], [Shoenfield 1967], [Boolos 1971], [Wang 1974], [Parsons 1977].

    Google Scholar 

  24. Comprehension obtains sets by dividing the universal class into two categories — objects that comply or do not comply with a given condition.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Von Neumann to Zermelo, August 1923, partly reproduced in [Meschkowski 1967, 28991].

    Google Scholar 

  26. The latter had already been stressed by Fraenkel, whose work seems to have guided many of von Neumann’s reflections.

    Google Scholar 

  27. [Meschkowski 1967, 290]: “Eine Menge ist dann und nur dann `zu gross’, wenn sie der Menge aller Dinge aequivalent ist.” In this letter, von Neumann employed naive terminology, as he would keep doing later, but it is clear that he was aware of the dangers.

    Google Scholar 

  28. In his opinion the development of the system became much simpler this way [1928a, 346; 1929, 494].

    Google Scholar 

  29. This is the “class theorem” proved in the first installment of Bernays’ series of papers, nowadays called theorem of predicative existence of classes.

    Google Scholar 

  30. In the 60s, Kripke, Cohen and Solovay, working independently, established that NBG with Global Choice is also a conservative extension of ZFC. The result was published later by Feigner [1971].

    Google Scholar 

  31. We shall not enter into more details regarding NBG here. Readers interested in a detailed analysis may turn, e.g., to [Fraenkel, Bar-Hillel & Levy 1973]. I would also like to emphasize that the historical interplay between ZFC and NBG ought to be the subject of more detailed research.

    Google Scholar 

  32. He refrained from publishing immediately, since he hoped to get further results regarding the independence of AC and CH (see Moore in [Gödel 1990, 158]).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Shepherdson [1951/53]. It was a very special inner model: the minimal one that contains all the ordinals and is transitive, i.e., such that, whenever x is in the model, so are elements of X.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Letter to Wang, 1968, in [Wang 1974, 10].

    Google Scholar 

  35. See the 1939 abstract in [Gödel 1990, 27]. Gödel writes Ma instead of the usual L a , and I have modernized his logical symbolism slightly.

    Google Scholar 

  36. As Solovay writes in [Gödel 1990, 8].

    Google Scholar 

  37. In ZF one writes: Vx3 a (xe L a ). Gödel’s axiom has been extensively studied by logicians, specially since the 60s; see Solovay in [Gödel 1990, 14–25].

    Google Scholar 

  38. Theorem 2 in [1938, 29]. This is the version of the axiom of reducibility that Gödel mentioned (see above). For further details, see Solovay in [Gödel 1990, 8–12] and [Gödel 1938].

    Google Scholar 

  39. In [1940], working within NBG, Gödel was able to give detailed proofs of his results without having to deal with metatheoretical notions within axiomatic set theory. The result, however, was a much less intuitive proof than the one offered for ZF in [1938]. Gödel himself admitted that the first exposition exhibited more clearly the basic idea of the proof in a note added in 1965 [Gödel 1940, 97] (see also Solovay in [Gödel 1990, 12–13]).

    Google Scholar 

  40. See [Moore 1988a], [Kanamori 1996] and Moore in [Godel 1990, 158–59]. Forcing is a powerful method, based on first-order logic, for defining models with prescribed properties.

    Google Scholar 

  41. As second-order logic can be seen to do, when the system is interpreted extensionally (§X.5).

    Google Scholar 

  42. I skip here over the issue of choosing between ZFC and NBG (see §3).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Another relevant but slightly earlier contribution is [Bemays 1935], which deals with Platonism in mathematics.

    Google Scholar 

  44. By the long sought proof of consistency of the theory of real numbers. As regards axiomatic set theory, von Neumann thought that a consistency proof was beyond reach [1929, 495].

    Google Scholar 

  45. See [Lakatos 1967], who calls this `quasi-empiricism,’ while I would prefer to speak of a hypothetical conception of (large parts of) mathematics. The most important popularizer of this view among philosophers has been Quine; see his [1953].

    Google Scholar 

  46. For Bourbaki’s hypothetical conception, see [1949, 3]. Perhaps I should mention that Bourbaki was no real person, but a fictitious character invented by a group of French mathematicians, who published their joint work under that name.

    Google Scholar 

  47. When the first volume of his treatise was published, Bourbaki [1954] had changed his axiom system slightly. Some indication of the difficulties can be found in [Corry 1996].

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Basel AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ferreirós, J. (1999). Consolidation of Axiomatic Set Theory. In: Labyrinth of Thought. Science Networks. Historical Studies, vol 23. Birkhäuser, Basel. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-0348-5049-0_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-0348-5049-0_11

  • Publisher Name: Birkhäuser, Basel

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-0348-5051-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-0348-5049-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics