Skip to main content

Personhood, Morality and Dignity in African Philosophy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
An African Ethics of Personhood and Bioethics
  • 300 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, Molefe articulates a personhood-based account of African ethics. He elaborates on the two facets of personhood as a moral theory—the agent-centred and patient-centred theories of value. In the first part of the chapter, he discusses the agent-centred theory of value. He accounts for it in terms of moral perfection, where the chief moral goal of the agent is to perfect her own humanity. He further unfolds the moral egoism, moral individualism and importance of social relationships associated with this moral system. The second part of the chapter focuses on the patient-centred facet of value—moral status or dignity. He begins by repudiating Polycarp Ikuenobe’s personhood-based view of dignity. Molefe proceeds to derive and construct a personhood-based account of dignity in the works of Ifeanyi Menkiti and Kwame Gyekye. Ultimately, he accounts for dignity in terms of the capacity for sympathy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In fact, the suggestion in this chapter is that the patient-centred idea of personhood informs the agent-centred notion of personhood.

  2. 2.

    I am aware that the reader might wonder why I do not separate these two facets of the ethics of personhood (the agent- and patient-centred) into different chapters. Initially, I thought I would do so. Upon careful consideration, however, I decided to capture these two facets of personhood in a single chapter. My decision is informed by two reasons. The first is philosophical in nature. The tendency in the literature in African philosophy is to discuss these two facets of the ethics of personhood separately, without imagining how they are related and what ethical consequences might ensue from their integration (see Behrens 2013; Oyowe 2018). For example, Behrens argues that the agent-centred notion is prevalent in the African tradition of philosophy and the patient-centred notion in the West. The unintended consequence of strictly associating them with these two philosophical might be to think that the one notion is African and the other notion is Western. The same logic manifests in Oyowe’s (2018) discussion of the strongly and weakly normative notions of personhood. Oyowe endorses the weakly normative notion of personhood, which is the same as the patient-centred notion of personhood (dignity), and he repudiates the agent-centred notion of personhood as implausible. I agree with both Behrens and Oyowe that these are two distinct normative notions, but I hold the view that these two facets of morality joined offer a fuller and more robust conception of the ethics of personhood. As such, to redress the tendency to discuss and imagine these two facets of the ethics of personhood separately, as if to suggest that they belong together in a single system of value, I discuss them in a single chapter to evince their interdependence and unity. I use the phrase the ethics of personhood to signal the fact that these two facets hang together in a single system of value. The second reason revolves around the fact that in other places, I have discussed these facets separately (see Molefe 2016, 2018a, 2019a). To keep the chapter’s length reasonable, I will not be exhaustive in my discussion of the agent-centred theory since I have elaborated on it in many other parts of my research (see Molefe 2018a, b, 2019a, b). The emphasis will be on the patient-centred facet since it is under-explored and is relevant to our philosophical quest to reflect on the themes of abortion and euthanasia.

  3. 3.

    Scholars of ubuntu/personhood tend to affirm the view that it amounts to a self-realisation/perfectionist moral view (Lutz 2009; Mokgoro 1998; Munyaka and Motlhabi 2009; Van Niekerk 2007, 2013).

  4. 4.

    I am aware that an egoistic interpretation might lend to the objection that one may kill an innocent individual for the sake of saving their own life, so that one is be able to pursue one’s personal perfection (see Metz 2007). The kind of egoism I associate with the idea of personhood is of a satisficing sort, which requires satisfactory perfection, and not that the agent must go all the way. The justification for this reading is derived from how scholars of personhood are committed to the dignity of every individual in the society, we ought to consider in the pursuit of moral perfection (see Wiredu 1996). Another justification of the satisficing-egoism is suggested by the commitment to social relationships, which implies that one cannot pursue moral perfection in ways that undermines social relationships. For a full discussion of the satisficing logic associated with personhood, see Molefe (2019a: 50).

  5. 5.

    Elsewhere, I offer a more extensive discussion of Ikuenobe’s novel view of dignity and its criticisms (see Molefe 2019b: ch. 6; 2020: ch. 3). In this chapter, I offer the reader a rough discussion of Ikuenobe’s view and its criticism. The major focus should be on the under-explored view of dignity grounded on the idea of personhood, which I associate with Menkiti and Gyekye.

  6. 6.

    One way to object to this way of reading Menkiti’s interpretation of dignity in terms of the capacity for moral sense is by pointing to those passages in his work that seem to be anti-essentialist regarding the definition of personhood. Remember, Menkiti (1984: 172) rejects what he refers to as the minimalist conception of personhood that defines personhood by reference to particular capacities or ontological features. I suspect this might be another reason why Ikuenobe eschews the essentialist definition of dignity, and instead defines it in terms of moral conduct. I think two responses will suffice to demonstrate that an essentialist interpretation of dignity is possible and inherent in Menkiti’s moral philosophy. Firstly, I cited instances in Menkiti’s own work where he proposes an essential view of moral status or dignity, which he uses to exclude animals from the moral community. For another reference that suggests an essentialist reading of dignity, consider this comment by Menkiti (2018: 18, emphasis mine)—“The individual counts and is ultimately the bearer of intrinsic value. Theorists need to be reminded of this fact, I concur, so that the structures they set up do not wind up sacrificing the individual in the pursuit of abstractions.” The claim that the individual is a bearer of intrinsic value is usually interpreted to mean that there is a capacity, possessed by the individual, in virtue of which it is inherently valuable. The point is that the value of the individual depends on the fact of her own existence as an individual. Social structures do not create this value; they only discover it and they ought to respect it. I advise the reader to note that it is at this very point that Gyekye (1992: 111) insists that essentialism is inescapable if Menkiti is true to how he characterises personhood. Gyekye says—“at this stage they are capable of exercising their moral sense and thus of making moral judgments. Menkiti, in fact, accepts the characterization or definition of personhood in terms of moral capacities. … This passage surely commits Menkiti to saying that a person is defined in terms of ‘some isolated static quality’—the quality of moral sense or capacity in the African case—which he thought was a characteristic of Western conceptions of personhood.” Finally, I believe that the passage where Menkiti is rejecting essentialism is ambiguous between whether he is referring to personal identity or moral status. If one reads Menkiti to be rejecting accounting for personal identity in essentialist terms, then it should mean he rejects essentialism en toto. When it comes to personal identity, he rejects essentialism, but when it comes to moral status, he espouses it.

  7. 7.

    It is crucial to notice that the phrase moral sense occurs at least six times in Gyekye’s adumbration of the idea of moral status that I believe is inherent in the agent-centred notion of personhood.

  8. 8.

    I am grateful to the reviewer for pointing me to the quotation where Menkiti cites pity [sympathy] as a central component of social justice.

  9. 9.

    In future research, the idea of sympathy in African moral thought still requires further philosophical elaboration and refinement to produce a precise theory of value, meta-ethically and normatively. One important suggestion emerging in this chapter is that the direction of our analysis should be towards an African sentimentalist view of ethics, rather than eudaimonism, as some scholars have suggested (Metz 2012a; Shutte 2001).

References

  • Agada, A. (2018). Language, Thought, and Interpersonal Communication: A Cross-Cultural Conversation on the Question of Individuality and Community. Filosofia Theoretica, 7, 141–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alison, H. (2010). The Beloved Self: Morality and the Challenge from Egoism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (1992). Ancient Ethics and Modern Morality. Philosophical Perspectives, 6, 119–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Behrens, K. (2010). Exploring African Holism with Respect to the Environment. Environmental Values, 9, 465–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Behrens, K. (2011). African Philosophy, Thought and Practice and Their Contribution to Environmental Ethics. Doctoral Dissertation. Johannesburg: University of Johannesburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behrens, K. (2013). Two ‘Normative’ Conceptions of Personhood. Quest, 25, 103–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, A., & Lo, Y. (2007). Two Conceptions of Human Dignity: Honour and Self-Determination. In J. Malpas & N. Lickiss (Eds.), Perspectives on Human Dignity: A Conversation. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bujo, B. (2001). Foundations of an African Ethic: Beyond the Universal Claims of Western Morality. New York: The Crossroad Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemhuru, M. (2016). The Import of African Ontology for Environmental Ethics. Johannesburg: University of Johannesburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (1977). Two Kinds of Respect. Ethics, 80, 36–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2008). Moral Status as a Matter of Degree? Southern Journal Philosophy, 46, 181–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2013). Equal Consideration and Unequal Moral Status. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 31, 17–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, J. (2009). Human Dignity and Human Rights. Denver: Josef Korbel School of International Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etieyibo, E. (2017). Anthropocentrism, African Metaphysical Worldview, and Animal Practices: A Reply to Kai Horsthemke. Journal of Animal Ethics, 7, 145–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eze, O. (2005). Ubuntu: A Communitarian Response to Liberal Individualism. Masters Dissertation. Pretoria: University of Pretoria.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eze, M. (2018). Menkiti, Gyekye, and Beyond: Towards a Decolonisation of African Political Philosophy. Filosofia Theoretica, 7, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gbadegesin, S. (1991). African Philosophy: Traditional Yoruba Philosophy and Contemporary African Realities. New York, NY: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gyekye, K. (1992). Person and Community in African Thought. In Person and Community: Ghanaian Philosophical Studies, 1 (pp. 101–122). Washington, DC: Council for Research in Values and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gyekye, K. (1995). An Essay on African Philosophical Thought: The Akan Conceptual Scheme. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gyekye, K. (1997). Tradition and Modernity: Philosophical Reflections on the African Experience. New York: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gyekye, K. (2010). African Ethics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 27, 2019, from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/african-ethics.

  • Horsthemke, K. (2015). Animals and African Ethics. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horsthemke, K. (2018). African Communalism, Persons, and Animals. Filosofia Theoretica, 7, 60–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. (2011). The Concept of Dignity in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Journal of Religious Ethics, 39, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, P. (1995). Getting Our Options Clear: A Closer Look at Agent-Centered Options. Philosophical Studies, 78, 163–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ikuenobe, P. (2006). Philosophical Perspectives on Communalism and Morality in African Traditions. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ikuenobe, P. (2015). Relational Autonomy, Personhood, and African Traditions. Philosophy East and West, 65, 1005–1029.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ikuenobe, P. (2017). The Communal Basis for Moral Dignity: An African Perspective. Philosophical Papers, 45, 437–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ikuenobe, P. (2018). Human Rights, Personhood, Dignity, and African Communalism. Journal of Human Rights, 17, 589–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaworska, A., & Tannenbaum, J. (2018). The Grounds of Moral Status. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 30, 2019, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/grounds-moral-status/.

  • Kant, E. (1785). Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten. Riga: Johann Frederich Hartknoch. English edition: Kant, E. (1998). Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (M. Gregor, Trans.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaphagawani, D. (2004). African Conceptions of a Person: A Critical Survey. In K. Wiredu (Ed.), A Companion to African Philosophy (pp. 332–442). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2018). Moral Sentimentalism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 27, 2019, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/moral-sentimentalism/.

  • Kymlicka, W. (1990). Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loschke, J. (2018). Relationships as Indirect Intensifiers: Solving the Puzzle of Partiality. European Journal of Philosophy, 26, 390–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Louw, D. (2004). Ubuntu and the Challenges of Multiculturalism in post-Apartheid South Africa. Utrecht: Centre for Southern Africa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, D. (2009). African Ubuntu Philosophy and Global Management. Journal of Business Ethics, 84, 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masolo, D. (2004). Western and African Communitarianism: In K. Wiredu (Ed.), A Comparison. Companion to African Philosophy. Blackwell Publishing: Oxford, 483–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masolo, D. (2010). Self and Community in a Changing World. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, T. (2014). Moral Individualism, Moral Relationalism and Obligations to Non-human Animals. Journal of Applied Ethics, 31, 155–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mbigi, L. (2005). The Spirit of African Leadership. Randburg: Knowers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mbiti, J. (1969). African Religions and Philosophy. New York, NY: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton, D., & Rawling, P. (2006). Deontology. In D. Copp (Ed.), Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory (pp. 425–458). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menkiti, I. (1984). Person and Community in African Traditional Thought. In R. A. Wright (Ed.), African Philosophy: An Introduction (pp. 171–181). Lanham, MD: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menkiti, I. (2004). On the Normative Conception of a Person. In K. Wiredu (Ed.), A Companion to African Philosophy (pp. 324–331). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menkiti, I. (2017). Africa and Global Justice. Philosophical Papers, 46, 13–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menkiti, I. (2018). Person and Community—A Retrospective Statement. Filosofia Theoretica, 7, 162–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2007). Toward an African Moral Theory. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 15, 321–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2010). Human Dignity, Capital Punishment and an African Moral Theory: Toward a New Philosophy of Human Rights. Journal of Human Rights, 9, 81–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2011). Ubuntu as a Moral Theory and Human Rights in South Africa. African Human Rights Law Journal, 11, 532–559.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2012a). Ethics in Aristotle and in Africa: Some Points of Contrast. Phronimon, 13, 99–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2012b). An African Theory of Moral Status: A Relational Alternative to Individualism and Holism. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice: An International Forum, 14, 387–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, T. (2013). Introduction: Engaging with the Philosophy of D.A. Masolo. Quest, 25, 7–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michael, L. (2014). Defining Dignity and Its Place in Human Rights. The New Bioethics, 20, 12–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, S. (2017). Reconsidering Dignity Relationally. Ethics and Social Welfare, 2, 108–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mokgoro, Y. (1998). Ubuntu and the Law in South Africa. Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal, 1, 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2015). A Rejection of Humanism in the African Moral Tradition. Theoria, 143, 59–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2016). Revisiting the Debate Between Gyekye-Menkiti: Who Is a Radical Communitarian? Theoria, 63, 37–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2017a). Individualism in African Moral Cultures. Cultura: International Journal of Philosophy of Culture and Axiology, 14, 49–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2017b). A Critique of Thad Metz’s African Theory of Moral Status. South African Journal of Philosophy, 36(2), 195–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2017c). Relational Ethics and Partiality: A Critique of Thad Metz’s ‘Towards an African Moral Theory’. Theoria, 64, 43–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2018a). Personhood and (Rectification) Justice in African Thought. Politikon, 45, 352–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2018b). Personhood and Rights in an African Tradition. Politikon, 45, 217–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2019a). An African Philosophy of Personhood, Morality and Politics. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2019b) Ubuntu and Development: An African Conception of Development. Africa Today 66: 96–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2019c). Solving the Conundrum of African Philosophy Through. Personhood: The Individual or Community. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-019-09683-8.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Molefe, M. (2020). African Personhood and Applied Ethics. Grahamstown: NISC [Pty].Ltd.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Munyaka, M. & Motlhabi, M. (2009). Ubuntu and Its Socio-Moral Significance. In F. M. Murove (Ed.), African Ethics: An Anthology of Comparative and Applied Ethics (pp. 324–331). Pietermaritzburg: University of Kwa-Zulu Natal Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, B. (1984). Environmental Ethics and Weak Anthropocentrism. Environmental Ethics, 6, 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2011). Creating Capabilities: The Human Development Approach. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neil, O. (1997). Environmental Values, Anthropocentrism and Speciesism. Environmental Values, 6, 127–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oyowe, A. (2014). Fiction, Culture and the Concept of a Person. Research in African Literatures, 45, 42–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oyowe, A. (2018). Personhood and Strong Normative Constraints. Philosophy East and West, 34, 783–801.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pannenberg, W. (1991). Systematic Theology (Vol. 2). Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paris, P. (1995). The Spirituality of African Peoples: The Search for a Common Moral Discourse. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pojman, L. (2002). What is Ethics? In L. Pojman (Ed.), Ethical Theory: Classic and Contemporary Readings (pp. 1–7). London: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J., & Rachels, S. (2015). The Elements of Moral Philosophy. Boston, MA: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramose, M. (1999). African Philosophy through Ubuntu. Harare: Mond Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramose, M. (2003). The Ethics of Ubuntu. In P. Coetzee & A. Roux (Eds.), The African Philosophy Reader (pp. 324–331). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, M. (2012). Dignity: Its History and Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sebidi, J. (1988). Towards the Definition of Ubuntu as African Humanism. Private Collection: Paper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shutte, A. (2001). Ubuntu: An Ethic for a New South Africa. Pietermaritzburg: Cluster Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (2010). Moral Sentimentalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toscano, M. (2011). Human Dignity as High Moral Status. The Ethics Forum, 6(2), 4–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tshivhase, M. (2013). Personhood: Social Approval or a Unique Identity? Quest: An African Journal of Philosophy, 25, 119–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tutu, D. (1999). No Future Without Forgiveness. New York, NY: Random House.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Niekerk, J. (2007). In Defence of an Autocentric Account of Ubuntu. South African Journal of Philosophy, 26, 364–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Niekerk, J. (2013). Ubuntu and Moral Theory. Johannesburg: University of the Witwatersrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (2012). Dignity, Rank and Rights. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wingo, A. (2006). Akan Philosophy of the Person. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved October 30, 2019, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/akan-person/.

  • Wiredu, K. (1980). Philosophy and an African Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, K. (1992). Moral Foundations of an African Culture. In K. Wiredu & K. Gyekye (Eds.), Person and Community: Ghanaian Philosophical Studies, 1 (pp. 192–206). Washington, DC: The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, K. (1996). Cultural Universals and Particulars: An African Perspective. Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, K. (2004). Introduction: African Philosophy in Our Time. In Companion to African Philosophy (pp. 1–27). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, K. (2008). Social Philosophy in Postcolonial Africa: Some Preliminaries Concerning Communalism and Communitarianism. South African Journal of Philosophy, 27, 332–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiredu, K. (2009). An Oral Philosophy of Personhood: Comments on Philosophy and Orality. Research in African Literatures, 40, 8–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (2007). Cross-Cultural Moral Philosophy: Reflections on Thaddeus Metz: ‘Toward an African Moral Theory’. South African Journal of Philosophy, 26, 337–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Motsamai Molefe .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Molefe, M. (2020). Personhood, Morality and Dignity in African Philosophy. In: An African Ethics of Personhood and Bioethics. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-46519-3_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics