Skip to main content

Wild Relationality: The Skin Is Not an Epistemic Border

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 189 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 56))

Abstract

The present paper questions whether or not metatheoretical approaches to cognitive science that utilize dynamical systems theory (DST) require a definitive means of demarcating the cognitive from the non-cognitive. As more researchers utilize DST as means to describe relational properties that emerge in an organism’s interaction with its environment and then utilize relational properties as an account of cognition, we are forced to clearly specify (1) how relational properties differ from non-relational (i.e., intrinsic) properties, and (2) what, if any, roles the two types of properties play in constituting cognition. According to Wild Systems Theory (WST), this intrinsic-relational tension lies at the heart of current debates regarding extended cognition. WST asserts that if DST allows us to see cognitive phenomena in terms of relational properties, and not intrinsic properties, it might be the case that discovering the ‘bounds of cognition’ was never a problem in need of solving.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

References

  • Adams F, Aizawa K (2001) The bounds of cognition. Philos Psychol 14(1):43–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson ML, Rosenberg G (2008) Content and action: the guidance theory of representation. J Mind Behav 29(1, 2):55–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Atmanspacher H (2007) Contextual emergence from physics to cognitive neuroscience. J Conscious Stud 14(1–2):18–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauer W (2011) An argument for the extrinsic grounding of mass. Erkenntnis 74(1):81–99. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-010-9269-4

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1993) Representational content in humans and machines. J Exp Theor Artif Intell 5:285–333

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop RC, Atmanspacher H (2006) Contextual emergence in the description of properties. Found Phys 36(12):1753–1777

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1996) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero A (2011) Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehmelt H (1989) Triton, electron, cosmon: an infinite regression? Proc Natl Acad Sci 86(22):8618–8619. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.88.4.1590a

  • Dretske F (1981) Knowledge and the flow of information. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1986) Misrepresentation. In: Bogdan R (ed) Belief: form, content, and function. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 17–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1988) Explaining behavior. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J (1981) Representations: philosophical essays on the foundations of cognitive science. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J (1987) Psychosemantics. The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1982) Conceptual role semantics. Notre Dame J Form Log 23:242–256

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1987) (Nonsolipsistic) conceptual role semantics. In: LePore E (ed) Semantics of natural language. Academic Press, New York, pp 55–81

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnad S (1990) The symbol grounding problem. Physica D 42(1–3):335–346

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré R (1986) Varieties of realism: a rationale for the natural sciences. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hebb DO (1949) The organization of behavior: a neuropsychological theory. Wiley, New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins E (2014) The cultural ecosystem of human cognition. Philos Psychol 27(1):34–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Jammer M (2009) Concepts of mass in contemporary physics and philosophy. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan JS (2008) Wild agency: nested intentionalities in cognitive neuroscience and archaeology. Philos Trans R Soc B: Biol Sci 363(1499):1981–1991

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan JS (2013) The wild ways of conscious will: what we do, how we do it, and why it has meaning. Front Psychol 4:574

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan JS, Cialdella VT, Dayer A, Langley MD, Stillman Z (2017) Wild bodies don’t need to perceive, detect, capture, or create meaning: they are meaning. Front Psychol 8:1149

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan JS, Day B (2015) Wild systems theory as a 21st century coherence framework for cognitive science. In: Metzinger T, Windt JM (eds) Open MIND: 21. MIND Group, Frankfurt am Main. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958570191

  • Jordan JS, Ghin M (2006) (Proto-) consciousness as a contextually emergent property of self-sustaining systems. Mind Matter 4(1):45–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan JS, Heidenreich BA (2010) The intentional nature of self-sustaining systems. Mind Matter 8(1):45–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan JS, Vinson D (2012) After nature: on bodies, consciousness, and causality. J Conscious Stud 19(5–6):229–250

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (1995) At home in the universe. Oxford University Press, New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemke J (2000) Across the scales of time: artifacts, activities, and meaning in eco-social systems. Mind Cult Act 7(4):273–290

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1980) Problems in the neurophysiology of cognition. In: Autopoiesis and cognition. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 41–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger T (2017) The problem of mental action: predictive control without sensory sheets. Johannes Gutenberg-Universität Mainz

    Google Scholar 

  • Odum HT (1988) Self-organization, transformity, and information. Science 242(4882):1132–1139. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.242.4882.1132

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior E, Pargetter R, Jackson F (1982) Three theses about dispositions. Am Philos Q 19(3):251–257

    Google Scholar 

  • Raja V, Biener Z, Chemero A (2017) From Kepler to Gibson. Ecol Psychol 29(2):146–160

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (1958) A relational theory of biological systems. Bull Math Biophys 20:245–260. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02478302

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (2000) Essays on life itself. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer J (2003) Is there a fundamental level? Noûs 37(3):498–517. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0068.00448

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger E (1944) What is life? The physical aspect of the living cell and mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Siewert C (2017) Consciousness and intentionality. In E. Zala’s (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/consciousness-intentionality

  • Silberstein M, Chemero A (2011) Dynamics, agency and intentional action. Humana Mente 15:1–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein M, Chemero A (2015) Extending neutral monism to the hard problem. J Conscious Stud 22(3–4):181–194

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner BF (1976) About behaviorism. Vintage Books, New York, NY

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith LB, Thelen E (2003) Development as a dynamic system. Trends Cognit Sci 7(8):343–348

    Google Scholar 

  • Streeck J, Jordan JS (2009) Communication as a dynamical self‐sustaining system: the importance of time‐scales and nested context. Commun Theory 19(4):445–464

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandervert L (1995) Chaos theory and the evolution of consciousness and mind: a thermodynamic-holographic resolution to the mind–body problem. New Ideas Psychol 13(2):107–127. https://doi.org/10.1016/0732-118x(94)00047-7

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Scott Jordan .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Jordan, J.S., Dayer, A., Mason, J., Cialdella, V. (2020). Wild Relationality: The Skin Is Not an Epistemic Border. In: Bertolotti, T. (eds) Cognition in 3E: Emergent, Embodied, Extended. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 56. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-46339-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics