Skip to main content

From Antiquity to the Middle Ages. Philosophy, Truth, and Demonstration

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Trust (Trust 2020)

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 54))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 504 Accesses

Abstract

A common saying of medieval Aristotelianism, both in Arabic and in Latin, labels Aristotle the “First Teacher”. This label implies not only that Aristotle established the system of sciences, but also that he created the demonstrative method. Against the background of the contemporary debates about demonstration and inquiry on natural phenomena in Aristotle, this article contends that the medieval pattern of the “First Teacher” is grounded in late Antiquity, and inherits from the vision of science elaborated first by Alexander of Aphrodisias, and then in the Neoplatonic school of Alexandria.

My most sincere thanks go to Concetta Luna. Her reading of a first draft of this paper saved me from many errors. I am also indebted to the anonymous referees for this volume, whose helpful criticisms are acknoweldged in the footnotes below and to whom I express here my heartfelt thanks. All the remaining shortcomings are mine.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Lloyd (1990), 371: “The question of the relationship between Aristotle’s theory of science set out in the Posterior Analytics and his actual practice in the physical treatises is, you will feel, a hoary old chestnut indeed. Faced with a series of apparent discrepancies between the two, starting with the notorious mismatch between the attention devoted to the theory of the syllogism in the Organon and evident lack of good-looking actual examples of syllogisms in the physical works, what are we to say?” I owe to one of the referees of this article the remark that Lloyd’s tenet is best accounted for against the background of his more general refusal to see Aristotle as engaged with the question of how to reach a systematic vision covering all the scientific fields. The same referee also points to Gotthelf’s reply to Lloyd in Gotthelf (2012), 185: both remarsk shed light on the issue at hand.

  2. 2.

    E.g. in Part. An. I 1, 639 b 8–10. See also An. Post. I 13, 78 b 39—79 a 5; De Cael. II 13, 293 a 23–30; III 7, 306 a 5–17; Metaph. XII 8, 1073 b 32–38.

  3. 3.

    Owen (1961).

  4. 4.

    Wieland (1960–61), English version (1975).

  5. 5.

    A further question that cannot be dealt with here is the relationship this debate has with that on the status of demonstrative science versus dialectic: cf. for instance Hamlyn (1990).

  6. 6.

    Barnes (1969, 1975), 77 and 85 (of the 1975 revised version): “The theory of demonstrative science was never meant to guide or formalise scientific research (…) it does not describe how scientists do, or ought to, acquire knowledge. (…) In developing the theory of demonstration and in constructing his notion of demonstrative science, Aristotle was not telling the scientist how to conduct his research: he was giving the pedagogue advice on the most efficient and economic method of bettering his charges. The theory of demonstration offers a formal account of how an achieved body of knowledge should be presented and taught”. As the earliest advocate of this solution, Barnes (fn. 70) quotes Grote (1880). Barnes’ interpretation is labelled “Teaching Thesis” by Wians (1989).

  7. 7.

    Burnyeat (1981) raises doubts about the existence of a ‘pedagogic’ approach in the Posterior Analytics, whose aim is rather to generate complete understanding of demonstrative truths about nature: only such a complete understanding meets the criteria to be a science, and complete understanding is not within the reach of a disciple. Barnes (1981) partly reformulates his position, and other critical remarks are advanced by Wians (1989), also against the revised version. One of the referees of this paper remarks that contemporary Aristotelian scholarship the “Teaching Thesis” is not seen as a viable solution to the “classical problem” mentioned above.

  8. 8.

    Significant contributions to the solution of the riddle include Bolton (1987 and 1991), Ferejohn (1990), Berti (1991), McKirahan (1992), Barnes (1993), Lennox (2001), Falcon (2005), Ebrey (2015), Falcon (2017).

  9. 9.

    Hadot (1987a, b), 14: “A partir du 1er siècle av. J.C., avec la ruine de la plupart des institutions philosophiques d’Athènes, provoquée par les dévastations de Sylla, avec la formation de nombreuses institutions philosophiques dans l’ensemble du Bassin méditerranéen, une seconde phase de l’histoire de la philosophie postsocratique se développe. Les quatre tendances doctrinales fondamentales subsistent, mais elles ne sont plus supportées par l’institution athénienne créée par les fondateurs. Pour affirmer leur fidélité au fondateur, le quatre écoles philosophiques, répandues dans différentes villes d’Orient et d’Occident, ne peuvent plus s’appuyer sur l’institution qu’il a créée, ni sur la tradition orale intérieure à l’école, mais uniquement sur les textes du fondateur. Les cours de philosophie consisteront donc avant tout dans des commentaires de ce texte”. Cf. also Donini (1994) and Sedley (1996). The Lyceum ceased to exist as an institution after Sulla’s conquest of Athens: cf. Lynch (1972), 192–207; as for the Platonic school, it is well known that the Platonists disagreed on the question whether or not with Arcesilaus of Pytane (d. 241 b.C.) the Academy continued to be the same school that had been founded by Plato; one thing however is sure, it ceased to exist as an institution after Sulla’s conquest.

  10. 10.

    Düring (1957); Moraux (1973), 3–94; Gottschalk (1987), 1083–1097, Barnes (1996), Hatzimichali (2016). My thanks go to one of the referees for directing me also to Primavesi (2007).

  11. 11.

    Sandbach (1985) argued that Aristotle was little known during the Hellenistic age; critical remarks on this position were advanced by Hahm (1991); see now Falcon (2016), and Bénatouïl (2016). On the rediscovery of the corpus, the sources that record the facts, and the many problems related to this, cf. above n. 10.

  12. 12.

    The role of Andronicus’ edition in the rebirth of Aristotelianism has been challenged by Barnes (1996), 66, as follows: “Nothing suggests that the ‘Roman edition’, done by Andronicus of Rhodes, revolutionized Aristotelian studies. His text of Aristotle left little mark on posterity. His work as orderer and arranger of the treatises was not epoch-making. (…) There is no reason to think that the Peripatetic renascence was any more dependent on books; and there is no reason to think that Andronicus played midwife at the rebirth”.

  13. 13.

    Hadot (1979).

  14. 14.

    I owe to one of the referees of this article the remark that we should be wary of speaking of subalternatio: subordination as discussed in the Posterior Analytics does not apply primarily to the relationship of a science to higher or lower ones; rather, it applies to the relationship between a science and its subfields. This is surely true, especially in consideration of Aristotle’s rejection of a unique overarching science, that results from the prohibition of kind-crossing explanations; however, there is a tension (not to be explored here) between this tenet and the theory of the “most architectonic science” of Metaphysics A 2 (see below note 15, and cf. McKirahan 1978).

  15. 15.

    An. Po. I 13, 78 b 35–39. For first philosophy, or metaphysics, as the overarching science that encompasses every other one because it investigates the first causes of the whole reality, see Metaph. A 2, 982 a 14—b 12.

  16. 16.

    R. Chiaradonna offered a useful discussion of this question and the various responses to it at the meeting of the Centre “Greco, arabo, latino” of the universities of Pisa—Padua—EPHE Paris held in Pisa, November 26–28, 2019, devoted to the tradition of Aristotle’s Meteorologica in late Antiquity and in the Arab and Latin worlds. On the issue of the biological works cf. Gotthelf and Lennox (1987) Devereux—Pellegrin (1990); on the Meteorology, see Wilson (2013), Scharle (2015).

  17. 17.

    Needless to say that the passage of the Meteorologica does not imply an order of composition, as if Aristotle had written first the Physics, then the De Caelo, then again the De Gen. Corr., and finally the Meteorologica: the point is discussed by Burnyeat (2004). On the relationship between the Parva naturalia and the De Anima cf. Sassi (2014), with discussion of previous literature; cf. also Bydén and Radovic (2018).

  18. 18.

    Hadot (1987a, b, 1991).

  19. 19.

    On the late Antique interpretations of Aristotle’s doctrine of demonstrative science see De Haas (2002), De Haas et al. (2010).

  20. 20.

    Hein (1985).

  21. 21.

    Hein (1985), 86–130.

  22. 22.

    On the so-called “enlarged Organon” of late Antiquity and its Syriac and Arabic fortune cf. Hugonnard-Roche (2007).

  23. 23.

    This commentary is lost in Arabic and has come down to us in Latin and Hebrew translations. The passage above is translated from the Latin version. We owe to Harvey (1985) an English translation of the Hebrew version of the Prologue.

  24. 24.

    Lack of space forbids the treatment of the connected topic of the so-called “enumeration of the sciences” in al-Fārābī, his predecessors, and the philosophers inspired by him—chiefly Avicenna. This “enumeration of the sciences” was one of the main conduits of the late Antique curriculum to the Latin Middle Ages, via Dominicus Gundissalinus.

  25. 25.

    On the rise and increasing importance of the demonstrative method as the distinctive feature of philosophy and in particular of the works of the “First Teacher” from al-Fārābī onwards see Endress (1990, 1997, 2002); a survey of the Posterior Analytics in Arabic philosophy is offered by Marmura (1990).

  26. 26.

    Once again, lack of space forbids to go further into details: the primacy of the most remote cause alluded to above is stated in the first proposition of the Liber de causis, a syllabus of 31 propositions allegedly by Aristotle, but in reality extracted from Proclus’ Elements of theology, which was translated into Arabic in the so-called “circle of al-Kindī” (Endress 1973). Basic information in D’Ancona and Taylor (2003).

  27. 27.

    For the sake of space I will omit here to discuss the question of the alternate translation that Averroes mentions here and there in his commentary.

  28. 28.

    On the topic of yaqīn al-burhān in relationship with the theory of demonstration in the Arabic reception of the Posterior Analytics, especially by al-Fārābī (d. 950), see Endress (2002) and Black (2006).

  29. 29.

    On James of Venice’s translation of the Posterior Analytics cf. Ebbesen (1977), Bloch (2008); on its reception, cf. Corbini (2006).

  30. 30.

    Albert the Great, De Quindecim problematibus, VI. Note however that Albert, in his commentary on the Physics, criticizes Averroes’ ‘divinization’ of Aristotle’s mind: if one believes that Aristotle was a god, one ought also believe that he never erred; if, on the contrary, one acknowledges he was but a man, one must also think that sometimes he was wrong (VIII, tract. 1, 14), a clear response to Averroes.

  31. 31.

    Lack of space forbids even to try to make good for the loss of a discussion of Albert the Great’s and Thomas Aquinas’ position, as remarked with good reason by one of the referees. Recent scholarship, taking into account previous contributions on the broad topic of the scholastic attitude towards Aristotle’s criteria for scientific knowledge, include Resnick (2013), Amerini and Galluzzo (2014), and Bydén and Thomsen-Thörnqvist (2017).

References

  • Amerini F, Galluzzo G (eds) (2014) A companion to the Latin Medieval commentaries on Aristotle’s metaphysics. Brill, Leiden-Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes J (1969) Aristotle’s theory of demonstration. Phronesis 14:123–152. Revised version In: Barnes J, Schofield JM, Sorabji R (eds) Articles on Aristotle, vol. 1. Science. London: Duckworth, pp 65–87

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes J (1981) Proof and the syllogism. In: Berti E (ed) Aristotle on science: the posterior analytics. Proceedings of the 8th symposium Aristotelicum. Padua, Antenore, pp 17–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes J (1993) Aristotle’s philosophy of the sciences. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 11:225–241

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes J (1996) Roman Aristotle. In: Barnes J, Griffin M (eds) Philosophia Togata. II. Plato and Aristotle at Rome. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 1–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Bénatouïl Th (2016) Aristotle and the Stoa. In Falcon A (ed) Brill’s companion to the reception of Aristotle in antiquity. Leiden–Boston, pp 56–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Berti E (1991) Les méthodes d’argumentation et de démonstration dans la Physique (apories, phénomènes, principes). In: De Gandt A, Souffrin P (eds) La Physique d’Aristote et les conditions d’une science de la nature. Vrin, Paris, pp 53–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Black DL (2006) Knowledge (‘ilm) and Certitude (yaqīn) in al-Fārābī’s Epistemology. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 16:11–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloch D (2008) James of venice and the posterior analytics. Cahiers de l’Institut du Moyen Age grec et latin 78:35–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton R (1987) Definition and scientific method in Aristotle’s posterior analytics and generation of animals. In: Gotthelf A, Lennox JG (eds) Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology. Cambridge, pp 120–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolton R (1991) Aristotle’s method in natural science: physics I. In: Judson L (ed) Aristotle’s physics. A collection of essays. Oxford, pp 2–29

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat M (1981) Aristotle on understanding knowledge. In: Berti E (ed) Aristotle on science: the posterior analytics. Proceedings of the 8th Symposium Aristotelicum. Padua. Antenore, pp 97–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat M (2004) Introduction: Aristotle on the foundation of sublunary physics. In: de Haas FAJ mansfeld j (ed) Aristotle’s on Generation and Corruption I. Symposium Aristotelicum, Oxford, pp 7–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Bydén B, Radovic F (eds) (2018) The Parva naturalia in Greek. Springer, Arabic and Latin Aristotelianism. Supplementing the Science of the Soul

    Google Scholar 

  • Bydén B, Thomsen-Thörnqvist Ch (eds) (2017) The Aristotelian tradition. Aristotle’s works on logic and metaphysics and their reception in the middle ages. Brepols, Turnhout

    Google Scholar 

  • Corbini A (2006) La teoria della scienza nel XIII secolo. I commenti agli Analitici secondi, Sismel—Edizioni del Galluzzo, Firenze

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Ancona C, Taylor RC (2003) Le Liber de causis. In: Goulet R (ed) Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques, I. CNRS Editions, Paris, pp 549–647

    Google Scholar 

  • De Haas FAJ (2002) Modifications of the method of inquiry in Aristotle’s physics I.1. An essay on the dynamics of the ancient commentary tradition. In: Leijenhorst CH, Leijenhorst C, Lüthy CH, Thijssen JMMH (eds) The dynamics of Aristotelian natural philosophy from Antiquity to the seventeenth century. Brill, Leiden, pp 31–56

    Google Scholar 

  • De Haas FAJ, Leunissen M, Martin M (eds) (2010) Interpreting Aristotle’s posterior analytics in late antiquity and beyond. Brill, Leiden-Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Devereux P, Pellegrin P (eds) (1990) Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote. CNRS Editions, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Donini P (1994) Testi e commenti, manuali e insegnamento: la forma sistematica e i metodi della filosofia in età postellenistica. In: Haase W, Temporini H (eds) Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt II.36.7. De Gruyter, Berlin–New York, pp 5017–5100

    Google Scholar 

  • Düring I (1957) Aristotle in the ancient biographical tradition, Almqvist & Wiksell, Göteborg & Stockholm

    Google Scholar 

  • Ebbesen S (1977) Iacobus veneticus on the posterior analytics and some early 13th Century Oxford masters on the Elenchi. Cahiers de l’Isntitut du Moyen Age grec et latin 21:1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Ebrey D (ed) (2015) Theory and practice in Aristotle’s natural science. Cambridge U.P, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Endress G (1973) Proclus Arabus. Zwanzig Abschnitte aus der Institutio Theologica in arabischer Übersetzung. Imprimerie Catholique, Wiesbaden-Beirut

    Google Scholar 

  • Endress G (1990) The defence of reason: the plea for philosophy in the religious community. Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Arabisch- Islamischen Wissenschaften 6:1–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Endress G (1997) L’Aristote arabe. Réception, autorité et transformation du ‘Premier Maître’, Medioevo 23:1–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Endress G (2002) The language of demonstration: translating science and the formation of terminology in Arabic philosophy and science. Early Science and Medicine 7:231–254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falcon A (2005) Aristotle and the science of nature: unity without uniformity. Cambridge U.P, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Falcon A (2016) Introduction. In Falcon A (ed) Brill’s Companion to the Reception of Aristotle in Antiquity. Leiden–Boston, pp 1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Falcon A (2017) Aristotelismo. Einaudi, Torino

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferejohn MT (1990) The origins of Aristotelian science. Yale U.P, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Gotthelf A (2012) Teleology, first principles, and scientific method in Aristotle’s biology. Oxford U.P, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gotthelf A, Lennox JG (eds) (1987) Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology. Cambridge U.P, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottschalk HB (1987) Aristotelian philosophy in the Roman world. In: Haase W, Temporini H (eds) Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt II.36.2. De Gruyter, Berlin–New York, pp 1079–1174

    Google Scholar 

  • Grote G (1880) Aristotle. Edited by Robertson GC, Bain A, 2nd ed. with additions. Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot I (1987a) La division néoplatonicienne des écrits d’Aristote. In: Wiesner J (ed) Aristoteles. Werk und Wirkung. Paul Moraux gewidmet. II: Kommentierung, Überlieferung, Nachleben. De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 249–285

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot I (1987b) Les introductions aux commentaires exégétiques chez les auteurs néoplatoniciens et les auteurs chrétiens. In: Tardieu M (ed) Les règles de l’interpretation, Cerf, Paris, pp 99–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot I (1991) The role of the commentaries on Aristotle in the teaching of philosophy according to the prefaces of the Neoplatonic commentaries on the categories. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Supplementary Volume. In: Blumenthal HJ, Robinson H. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 175–189

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot P (1979) Les divisions des parties de la philosophie dans l’Antiquité. Museum Helveticum 36:202–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot P (1987) Théologie, exégèse, révélation, Écriture dans la philosophie grecque. In: Tardieu M (ed) Les règles de l’interprétation. Cerf, Paris, pp 13–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahm DH (1991) Aristotle and the stoics: a methodological crux. Geschichte der Philosophie 73:771–791

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlyn DW (1990) Aristotle on dialectic. Philosophy 65:465–476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey S (1985) The Hebrew translation of Averroes’ Prooemium to his long commentary on Aristotle’s physics. Proceedings of the American Academy for Jewish Research 52:55–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hatzimichali M (2016) Andronicus of Rhodes and the construction of the Aristotelian corpus. In: Falcon A (ed) Brill’s companion to the reception of Aristotle in antiquity. Leiden–Boston, pp 81–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Hein Ch (1985) Definition und Einteilung der Philosophie. Von der spätantiken Einleitungsliteratur zur arabischen Enzyklopädie. P. Lang, Frankfurt, Bern-New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hugonnard-Roche H (2007) Le corpus philosophique syriaque aux VIe-VIIe siècles. In: D’Ancona C (ed) The libraries of the Neoplatonists. Proceedings of the Meeting of the European Science Foundation Network “Late Antiquity and Arabic Thought. Patterns in the Constitution of European Culture”, Brill, Leiden–Boston, pp 279–291

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (2001) Aristotle's philosophy of biology: studies in the origins of life science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd GER (1990) The theories and practices of demonstration in Aristotle. The Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 6, 371–401. Reprinted with additional notes and a Postscriptum in Lloyd GER (1996) Aristotelian explorations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 7–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch JP (1972) Aristotle’s school. A study of a Greek educational institution. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmura ME (1990) The fortuna of the posterior analytics in the Arabic middle ages. In: Astzalos M, Murdoch J, Niinliuoto I (eds) Knowledge and the sciences in medieval philosophy. Proceedings of the Eighth International Congress of Medieval Philosophy. S.I.E.P.M., Helsinki, pp 85–103

    Google Scholar 

  • McKirahan RD (1978) Aristotle’s subordinate sciences. The British Journal for the History of Science 11:197–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKirahan RD (1992) Principles and proofs. Aristotle’s theory of demonstrative science. Princeton U.P., Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Moraux P (1973) Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen von Andronikos bis Alexander von Aphrodisias. Band 1. Die Renaissance des Aristotelismus im 1. Jh. v. Chr. De Gruyter. Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen GEL (1961) Τιθέναι τὰ φαινόμενα. In: Mansion S (ed) Aristote et les problèmes de méthode. Symposium Aristotelicum. Louvain, pp 83–103. Reprinted In: Moravcsik JM (ed) (1967) Aristotle. A collection of critical essays. Doubleday, New York, pp 167–190. In: Barnes J, Schofield JM, Sorabji R (eds) (1975) Articles on aristotle, vol 1, Science, pp 113–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Primavesi O (2007) Ein Blick in den Stollen von Skepsis: Vier Kapitel zur frühen Überlieferung des Corpus Aristotelicum. Philologus 151:51–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Resnick IM (ed) (2013) A companion to Albert the great. Theology, Philosophy, and the Sciences. Brill, Leiden–Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandbach FH (1985) Aristotle and the Stoa. Cambridge Philological Society, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sassi MM (2014) Percezione e conoscenza nei Parva naturalia. Studia graeco-arabica 4:265–274

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharle M (2015) “And these things follow”: Teleology, necessity, and explanation in aristotle’s meteorologica. In: Ebrey D (ed) Theory and practice in aristotle’s natural science. Cambridge U.P., Cambridge, pp 79–99

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedley D (1996) Plato’s auctoritas and the rebirth of the commentary tradition. In: Barnes J, Griffin M (eds) Philosophia Togata. II. Plato and Aristotle at Rome. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 110–129

    Google Scholar 

  • Wians W (1989) Aristotle, demonstration, and teaching. Ancient Philosophy 9:245–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wieland W (1960–1961) Das Problem des Prinzipienforschung und die aristotelische Physik. Kant-Studien 52:206–219. English version: Aristotle’s Physics and the Problem of Inquiry into Principles. In: Barnes J, Schofield JM, Sorabji R (eds) Articles on Aristotle, vol. 1. Science. London, Duckworth, pp 127–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson M (2013) Structure and method in Aristotle’s meteorologica: a more disorderly nature. Cambridge U.P, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

Primary Sources

  • Albertus Magnus, Albertus Magnus, Physica, V-VIII edidit P. Hossfeld, in Alberti Magni Opera Omnia IV/1, Aschendorff, Münster 1993

    Google Scholar 

  • Albertus Magnus, De XV Problematibus edidit A. Hufnagel, in Alberti Magni Opera Omnia XVII/1, Aschendorff, Münster 1975

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexandri in Aristotelis Meteorologicorum libros commentaria (…) edidit M. Hayduck, Reimer, Berlin 1899 (CAG III, 2)

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle De Anima recognovit (...) W.D. Ross, Clarendon Press, Oxford 1956

    Google Scholar 

  • Arabic Translation: ʿA. Badawī (ed.), Arisṭūṭālīs fī l-nafs. al-Ārāʾ al-ṭabīʿiyya al-mansūb ilā Fulūṭarḫus. al-Ḥāss wa-l-maḥsūs li-Ibn Rušd. al-Nabāt al-mansūb ilā Arisṭūṭālīs, Maktabat al-nahḍa al-miṣriyya, Cairo 1954. Reprint Kuwayt/Beirut 1980, esp. pp. 3–88 (= Kitāb Arisṭāṭālīs wa-naṣṣ kalāmihī fī l-nafs. Tarǧamat Isḥāq ibn Ḥunayn)

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle Meteorologica with an English Translation by H.D.P. Lee, Harvard U.P.–Heinemann, Cambridge (MA) London 1952

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotelis Opera cum Averrois commentariis, Venetiis apud Junctas, 1562–1574 (reprin. Minerva, Frankfurt a.M. 1962), vol. IV, Aristotelis de Physico auditu libri octo cum Averrois Cordubensis (…) commentariis

    Google Scholar 

  • Averrois Cordubensis, Commentarium magnum in Aristotelis De Anima libros recensuit F.S. Crawford, Cambridge [MA] 1953 (Corpus Commentariorum Auerrois in Aristotelem … Versionum Latinarum VI 1)

    Google Scholar 

  • Averroes (Ibn Rushd) of Cordoba, Long Commentary on the De Anima of Aristotle. Translated and with Introduction and Notes by R.C. Taylor with Th.-A. Druart, subeditor, Yale U.P., New Haven–London 2009

    Google Scholar 

  • Ioannis Philoponi In Aristotelis Meteorologicorum librum primum commentarium (…) edidit M. Hayduck, Reimer, Berlin 1901 (CAG XIV, 1)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kupreeva I (2011) Philoponus: on Aristotle meteorology 1. 1–3. Translated by I. K., Bloomsbury, 507 London–New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasā’il al-Kindī al-falsafiyya, Dār al-fikr al- ‘arabī, vol. I, Cairo 1950

    Google Scholar 

  • The Philosophical Works of al-Kindī, P. Adamson and P. Pormann (trans.), Oxford U.P., Oxford–New York 2012

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cristina D’Ancona .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

D’Ancona, C. (2020). From Antiquity to the Middle Ages. Philosophy, Truth, and Demonstration. In: Fabris, A. (eds) Trust. Trust 2020. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 54. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-44018-3_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics