Skip to main content

Trust and Fiduciary Power

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Trust (Trust 2020)

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 54))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 514 Accesses

Abstract

This paper analyzes an aspect of trust relatively less explored by political philosophers, namely, the legal conception of trust. As I explain in Sect. 1, the legal conception of trust refers to trust as a moral and/or legal obligation of power. It is distinct from trust understood as confidence and from trustworthiness; nonetheless, I offer that trust as confidence is constitutive of trust as obligation. In Sect. 2, I briefly recount the origin of the trust and the development of the legal metaphor of trust in 17th century England, most notably in the work of John Locke. In Sect. 3, I turn to examining the contemporary fiduciary political theory proposed by Evan Fox-Decent, which is a literalist transposition of private fiduciary principle to the public sphere. One notable aspect of Fox-Decent’s theory is its attempt to justify the State’s legitimacy on the basis of its fiduciary relationship with its subjects. Fox-Decent thus offers an alternative to all consent-based theories, primarily contesting A. John Simmons’s voluntarism. As I explain in Sect. 4, fiduciary political theory is based on a “presumption of trust” and appeals to Annette Baier’s conception of an “unconscious, automatic” trust in order to explain the fiduciary relation between the individual and the irresistible administrative power of the State. In Sect. 5, I present the main objections to fiduciary political theory and explore the compatibility of the fiduciary principle with Simmons’s voluntarism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Braithwaite’s statement finds further confirmation in the work of J. S. Maloy. As the latter summarizes (2009), the recent literature on trust produced by political philosophers and scientists, when considering the specifically political dimensions or aspects of trust, has analyzed and examined the subject by mainly assuming a “psychic approach.” Authors mostly see trust as a “psychic quantity,” which becomes “political” when it regards institutions and politicians, or the relationship between politicians and ordinary citizens, or between the citizens themselves. The “psychic approach” also implies an “economic” understanding of trust, in the sense that it is seen “as a kind of resource amenable to increase, conservation, depletion, etc.” (Maloy 2009, 493). This approach then splits, according to Maloy, into two major diverging orientations: on the one hand, the “civic” or “social capital” line, epitomized by Robert D. Putnam; and on the other, the “legalistic” or “game-theoretical” line, epitomized by Russell Hardin. While the civic orientation tends to focus on the relationships between citizens and the social practices of mutual and/or generalized confidence that support healthy democratic life, the legalistic orientation, conversely, tends to focus on the relationship between citizens and institutions, and considers the ways in which institutions must be conceived in order to be supportive of general trust. In other words, according to the legalistic orientation, institutions represent the conditions “under which it is rationally justifiable to trust” (Maloy 2009, 493).

  2. 2.

    Previously it was assumed that “offices granted by the king were held ‘on trust and confidence’” (as stated in a Year Book of 1471, quoted in Seipp 2011, 1025, my emphasis).

  3. 3.

    So, the community is the wielder of actual sovereign power, as noted in Knoll (2010, 236). It is also for a similar reason that Jean Hampton proposes that what Locke had in mind was not a trustee/beneficiary relationship, but a principal/agent one (see Hampton 1986, 248n18). The latter is a fiduciary relationship based on a contract in which the principal controls the agent (see also Pettit 2012, 32).

  4. 4.

    On Burke, see Conniff (1977, 1993).

  5. 5.

    On this point see Foa Dienstag (1996).

  6. 6.

    “Sovereign power…upon the principle of utility, can never be other than fiduciary” (Bentham 2005, 263). “In whatever way we define or understand the idea of a right, no person can have a right…to power over others: every such power, which he is allowed to possess, is morally, in the fullest force of the term, a trust” (Mill 1998, 353–54).

  7. 7.

    The term was introduced by Leib et al. (2013, 91); on Finn’s contribution see Leib et al. (2014, 396); for a comprehensive theoretical introduction see Frankel (2011).

  8. 8.

    A comparison should be made with Philip Pettit’s contestatory republicanism (Pettit 1997). While Fox-Decent’s idea of the subject’s legal inability to exercise or control the administrative power of the State seems to be at odds with Pettit’s approach, the same cannot be said about Fox-Decent’s common law constitutionalism as a republican guarantee against domination (cfr. Fox-Decent 2011, 26).

  9. 9.

    Voluntarism is a political theory that grounds political obligation on express consent alone; see Simmons (1981).

  10. 10.

    Simmons distinguishes between justification and legitimacy of the State in his classic article Justification and Legitimacy. According to Simmons, “we can justify the state by showing that some realizable type of state is on balance morally permissible (or ideal) and that it is rationally preferable to all feasible nonstate alternatives” (Simmons 2001, 125–26), while “[p]olitical power is morally legitimate, and those subject to it are morally obligated to obey, only where the subjects have freely consented to the exercise of such a power and only where that power continues to be exercised within the terms of the consent given” (Simmons 2001, 129). Simmons specifies that “State legitimacy…includes an exclusive power over subjects to impose duties and enforce them coercively, which correlates with obligations on others to refrain from these tasks. It also includes a right, held against subjects, to be obeyed…This latter right is the logical correlate of subjects’ political obligations” (Simmons 2001, 130n20). It must be noted that in a previous article, Fox-Decent specified that his “claim regarding the legitimacy implied by state legal authority is much narrower in scope and ambition than the all-things-considered legitimacy that Simmons addresses…My project concerns solely the legitimatizing effects of legality…a state’s compliance with the fiduciary view of the rule of law gives the subject a reason to obey the law” (Fox-Decent 2005, 290, emphasis in the original). In his later magnum opus, Fox-Decent seems to offer a more radical view.

  11. 11.

    “The clearest case of agency of necessity involves shipmasters who find themselves in an emergency situation that places the cargo they are carrying in imminent peril…Shipmasters normally have no contract with the owners of the cargo. Nonetheless, courts have held that the shipmaster may act without prior authority as an agent of the cargo’s owner in order to protect the goods or their value” (Fox-Decent 2011, 132, my emphasis).

References

  • Adams J (1851) The works of John Adams, vol III. Charles C, Little and James Brown, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Ames JB (1908) The origins of uses and trusts. Harvard Law Review. 21:261–274. https://doi.org/10.2307/1324734

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baier A (1986) Trust and antitrust. Ethics. 96:231–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker E (1962) Social contract. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham J (2005) An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite J (1998) Institutionalizing trust, enculturating trust. In: Braithwaite V, Levi M (eds) Trust and governance. Russell Sage Foundation, New York, pp 343–375

    Google Scholar 

  • Conniff J (1977) Burke, Bristol, and the concept of representation. West Polit Quart. 30:329–341

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conniff J (1993) Burke and India: the failure of the theory of trusteeship. Polit Res Q 46:291–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Wilde M (2011) Fides publica in Ancient Rome and its reception by Grotius and Locke. Tijdschrift voor Rechtsgeschiedenis. 79:455–487. https://doi.org/10.1163/157181911X596394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn J (1984) The concept of ‘Trust’ in the politics of John Locke. In: Rorty R, Schneewind JB, Skinner Q (eds) Philosophy in history: essays on the historiography of philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 279–301

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Finn P (1995) The forgotten “Trust”: the people and the state. In: Cope M (ed) Equity: issues and trends. Federation Press, Sydney, pp 131–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Foa Dienstag J (1996) Between history and nature: social contract theory in Locke and the founders. J Politics 58:985–1009. https://doi.org/10.2307/2960146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox-Decent E (2005) The fiduciary nature of state legal authority. Queen’s Law J 31:259–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox-Decent E (2011) Sovereignty’s promise. The state as fiduciary. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fox-Decent E (2012) Hobbes’s relational theory. Between power and consent. In: Dyzenhaus D, Poole T (eds) Hobbes and the law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 118–144. https://doi.org/10.1017/cbo9781139137034.007

  • Frankel T (2011) Fiduciary law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Galoob SR, Leib EJ (2018a) Fiduciary political theory and legitimacy. In: Criddle EJ, Fox-Decent E, Gold AS, Kim SH, Miller PB (eds) Fiduciary government. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 163–182. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108155267.008

  • Galoob SR, Leib EJ (2018b) The core of fiduciary political theory. In: Gordon Smith D, Gold AS (eds) Research handbook on fiduciary law. Elgar, Cheltenham-Northampton, pp 401–417

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gold AS (2013) Reflections on the state as fiduciary. Univ Toronto Law Journal. 63:655–670

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gold AS (2018) The state as a wrongful fiduciary. In: Criddle EJ, Fox-Decent E, Gold AS, Kim SH, Miller PB (eds) Fiduciary government. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 183–202. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108155267.009

  • Gough J (1950) John Locke’s political philosophy: eight studies. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gvelesiani I (2016) In-depth analysis of the historical terms related to the common law “Trust”. Chall Knowl Soc 6:164–169

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton J (1986) Hobbes and the social contract tradition. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Knoll M (2010) John Locke als Vordenker der Grundprinzipien des democratischen Verfassungsstaates. In: Salzborn S (ed) Der Staat des Liberalismus: die Liberale Staatstheorie von John Locke. Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 211–244

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laslett P (1988) Introduction. In: Locke J (ed) Two treatises of government. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 3–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Leib EJ, Ponet DL (2011) Fiduciary law’s lessons for deliberative democracy. Boston Univ Law Rev 91:1207–1219

    Google Scholar 

  • Leib EJ, Ponet DL, Serota M (2013) Translating fiduciary principles into public law. Harvard Law Rev Forum 126:91–101

    Google Scholar 

  • Leib EJ, Ponet DL, Serota M (2014) Mapping public fiduciary relationships. In: Gold AS, Miller PB (eds) Philosophical foundations of fiduciary law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 388–403

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Locke J (1988) Two treatises of government. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luisi N (2016) Brevi considerazioni sull’origine romanistica della struttura negoziale del trust. Studi Urbinati, A - Scienze giuridiche, politiche ed economiche 69:51–131. https://doi.org/10.14276/1825-1676.536

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maitland FW (1910) Equity: also the forms of action at common law. Cambridge University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Maloy JS (2009) Two concepts of trust. J Politics 71:492–505. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0022381609090410

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1998) On liberty and other essays. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller PB (2016) Principles of public fiduciary administration. In: Kahana T, Scolnicov A (eds) Boundaries of state, boundaries of rights human rights, private actors, and positive obligations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 251–270. https://doi.org/10.1017/cbo9781107588943

  • Nacol EC (2011) The risks of political authority: trust, knowledge and political agency in Locke’s second treatise. Polit Stud 59:580–595. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2010.00878.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P (1997) Republicanism. A theory of freedom and government. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit PH (2012) Equity and the law of trusts. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seipp DJ (2011) Trust and fiduciary duty in the early common law. Boston Univ Law Rev 91:1011–1037

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons AJ (1981) Voluntarism and political associations. Virg Law Rev 67:19–37. https://doi.org/10.2307/1072830

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons AJ (1987) The anarchist position. A reply to Klosko and Senor. Philos Public Aff 16:269–279

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons AJ (1993) On the edge of anarchy. Locke, consent, and the limits of society. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons AJ (2001) Justification and legitimacy. Essays on rights and obligations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Windeknecht RG (2012) Law without legitimacy or justification? The flawed foundations of philosophical anarchism. Res Publica 18:173–188. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-011-9175-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zuckert MP (1994) Natural rights and the new republicanism. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Menon .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Menon, M. (2020). Trust and Fiduciary Power. In: Fabris, A. (eds) Trust. Trust 2020. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 54. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-44018-3_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics