Skip to main content

Can Education Be Egalitarian? Musonius Rufus and Julia Kristeva on Gendered Labor

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Stoic Philosophy and Social Theory
  • 309 Accesses

Abstract

The parameter of gender is useful in asking whether access to education and the work outcomes that derive from education are egalitarian. This discussion integrates Musonius’ belief that women deserve the same educational opportunities as men. Musonius qualifies this position with the condition that educated women must not abandon their domestic labor duties. I compare Musonius’ argument with Kristeva’s critique of what is only conditionally equal for women in the present-day. Women have benefited from feminism’s preceding incursions into patriarchal structures in receiving greater access to education and professional roles. Because such women do not relinquish domestic roles though, Kristeva argues that their experience of time is different from men’s. My consequent focus on time marks the original contribution this chapter makes to existing literature that is concerned with the complications in Musonius’ impression of gender equality. I apply Kristeva’s demand to recognize the differences between male and female temporalities to Musonius’ assertion of a singular virtue for men and women. An evaluation manifests that in terms of time there is not a singular Stoic virtue structure for men and women. From this, I ask whether the modern woman must problematically embody a Stoic indifference to inegalitarian time.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Linda Brodkey and Michelle Fine interpret that this gender disparity means that science affords males the belief that they alone legislate the human knowledge of reality (Brodkey and Fine 1992, 80). Janet Kourany reframes the debate by attending to the differences in gender disparities between various academic fields (Kourany 2012, 251). In Reflections on Gender and Science Evelyn Keller considers whether modern gender disparities simply continue the composition of Plato’s Academy (Keller 1985, 25). See Yeandle (2017) for a more recent discussion of the perpetuation of philosophy’s male domination.

  2. 2.

    The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) informs that “millions of girls around the world are still being denied an education” (UNESCO 2013). Its report identifies a global trend in which “two thirds of the 774 million illiterate people in the world are female” (2013). This prevention of access to basic education also occurs at a tertiary level, particularly in fields that lead to “skilled” vocations. D. Kelly Weisberg argues that historically “one of the paramount concerns of any skilled profession is the regulation of access to the profession” (Weisberg 1977, 485). Weisberg complementarily highlights the struggle women have had “to gain entrance to the legal profession” (485). Madeleine Arnot, Miriam David, and Gaby Weiner also recognize the structural exclusion of women from secondary and tertiary education programs. Their focus furthermore comprises which state policies have been implemented to address these inequalities (Arnot et al. 1999, ix).

  3. 3.

    There are brief examples of other Stoic philosophers also arguing for equal appreciations of men and women. Diogenes Laërtius reports that in his Republic Zeno makes the demand that we perceive men and women as equal given that they are “in common among the wise” (Diogenes Laërtius 1853, 7.66). Epictetus in Discourses posits that of a wise man he sees “no reason why he should not marry and have children” and that “his wife will be wise, like him” (Epictetus 2008, 3.22, 68). Diogenes additionally advises of Antisthenes’ tendency to assert that “virtue is the same in a man as in a woman” (Diogenes Laërtius 1853, 6.5). Given that Antisthenes was a student of Socrates, and taught Zeno’s teacher Crates of Thebes, this provides a possible link between Socrates’ views on women and the perspectives of the earliest Stoics. Plato’s Republic indeed details how Socrates proposes that women are as “philosophic” as men (Plato 2012, 6.1.456a) and as capable of fulfilling the city’s most prominent roles such as “guard and other duties” (6.1.451d). Donald Dudley doubts such a link between Socrates and Zeno however. Dudley claims that the Stoics fabricated accounts connecting Antisthenes to Zeno to create the impression of an unbroken sequence between Socrates and Zeno (Dudley 1937, 2–4). Of relevance to all the above is Malin Grahn-Wilder’s chapter “The Stoics on Equal Educability of Girls and Boys, and the Origin of Gendered Characteristics” taken from her Gender and Sexuality in Stoic Philosophy. Musonius’ assertion in Grahn-Wilder’s view regarding the equal treatment of women and men “follows naturally from premises commonly accepted by Stoic thinkers from Zeno to the Romans” (Grahn-Wilder 2018, 10).

  4. 4.

    James Dillon provides a comprehensive account of Musonius’ “three rounds of exile, two under Nero and one under Vespasian” (Dillon 2004, 6). The way that Musonius responds to each of these periods of banishment motivates Dillon to describe such experiences as revealing “of the congruence of his teaching and living” (6). One such banishment sends Musonius to the notoriously desolate island of Gyara or Gyaros. Despite this “Musonius lived cheerfully” (6) whereas other exiles had to be condemned to less brutal locations.

  5. 5.

    Cynthia King records in the “Translator’s Introduction” to her presentation of Musonius’ thought that he taught Epictetus after having been exiled by Vespasian and then returning under the rule of Titus (King in Musonius Rufus 2011, 13). Epictetus describes on multiple occasions the relationship with his Stoic master Musonius. One such example in Discourses is where Epictetus recalls how “Musonius used to test me by saying, ‘your master is going to afflict you with some hardship or other’” (1.9, 29). See also Reydams-Schils (2017, 157) and Long (2002, 13–17) for further explanations of the Musonius-Epictetus connection.

  6. 6.

    Diogenes Laërtius’ commentary on Chrysippus exemplifies this point. Chrysippus clarifies that a life in accordance with nature will be virtuous and happy; “the chief good is to live in a manner corresponding to nature” (Diogenes Laërtius 1853, 7.53). This counters the interpretation that posits virtue or happiness as ends to target. Happiness is “supervened” through being virtuous, which itself is supervened through a life “corresponding to one’s own nature and to the universal nature” (7.53).

  7. 7.

    I am not the first commentator to offer this reading of Musonius’ thought. Scott Aikin and Emily McGill-Rutherford’s article “Stoicism, Feminism and Autonomy” (2014) addresses aspects of Musonius’ theory in ways that are not dissimilar to the discussion I have presented. Edward Arnold’s Roman Stoicism (1911) also reveals these issues, as does Elizabeth Asmis’ chapter “The Stoics on Women” (1996). For a broader discussion of the complications of applying Musonius’ philosophy to modern feminist theory, see Martha Nussbaum’s chapter that we have already encountered—“The Incomplete Feminism of Musonius Rufus, Platonist, Stoic, and Roman” (Nussbaum 2002).

  8. 8.

    Fletcher and Benjamin (1990) provide one of the more useful collections of commentaries on Kristeva’s many foci.

  9. 9.

    Kurt Lampe gives a comprehensive account of Kristeva’s interest in Stoicism from a semiological perspective. Not incidentally given our choice of Stoic protagonist in this chapter, Lampe here integrates other features of Musonius’ philosophy such as his positions on eating meat (Lampe 2016, 34–35).

  10. 10.

    Marlene LeGates’ In Their Time: A History of Feminism in Western Society illuminates the reasons for this problematically conditional success of first-wave feminism. Legates’ chapter “Issues in First-Wave Feminism” (LeGates 2001, 237–280) particularly helps us to understand how the first wave’s inadequacies bred the differently oriented, second wave.

  11. 11.

    More adventurously, Brad Inwood asserts that because of these publicly practical orientations Musonius was likely not a Stoic philosopher whatsoever. Inwood characterizes him instead as a “generic philosopher” and “public intellectual” (Inwood 2017, 257).

  12. 12.

    For Rita Felski this means that women are now included in, rather than marginalized from, linear time. This in her estimation is no advantage as women now have to be more concerned with linear time and “more preoccupied with time measurement, than men” (Felski 2000, 20). The reason for this greater time-preoccupation is that the modern era has seen women relinquish few of their time-demanding domestic responsibilities while now also working full-time professional hours.

References

  • Aikin, Scott, and Emily McGill-Rutherford. 2014. Stoicism, Feminism and Autonomy. Symposium 1 (1): 9–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, Edward. 1911. Roman Stoicism: Being Lectures on the History of the Stoic Philosophy with Special Reference to Its Development Within the Roman Empire. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnot, Madeleine, Miriam David, and Gaby Weiner. 1999. Closing the Gender Gap: Postwar Education and Social Change. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asmis, Elizabeth. 1996. The Stoics on Women. In Feminism and Ancient Philosophy, ed. Julie Ward, 68–92. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brodkey, Linda, and Michelle Fine. 1992. Presence of Mind in the Absence of Body. In What Schools Can Do: Critical Pedagogy and Practice, ed. Kathleen Weiler and Candace Mitchell, 75–94. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Ste. Croix, G.E.M. 1981. The Class Struggle in the Ancient Greek World. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dillon, James. 2004. Musonius Rufus and Education in the Good Life: A Model of Teaching and Living Virtue. Dallas; Lanham; Boulder; New York; Oxford: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diogenes Laërtius. 1853. The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers. Translated by Charles Yonge. London: Henry G. Bohn Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dudley, Donald. 1937. A History of Cynicism: From Diogenes to the 6th Century A.D. London: Methuen & Co. Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, David. 2000. The Gender Egalitarianism of Musonius Rufus. Ancient Philosophy 20: 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epictetus. 2008. Discourses and Selected Writings. Translated by Robert Dobbin. Oxford: Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Discourses, Fragments, and Handbook. Translated by Robin Hard. Introduction and Notes by Christopher Gill. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felski, Rita. 2000. Doing Time: Feminist Theory and Postmodern Culture. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, John, and Andrew Benjamin (ed.). 1990. Abjection, Melancholia, and Love: The Work of Julia Kristeva: Volume 4. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1985 (1984). The Care of the Self: The History of Sexuality Volume 3. Translated by Robert Hurley. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grahn-Wilder, Malin. 2018. Gender and Sexuality in Stoic Philosophy. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Inwood, Brad. 2017. The Legacy of Musonius Rufus. In From Stoicism to Platonism: The Development of Philosophy, 100 BCE–100 CE, ed. Troels Engberg-Pedersen, 254–276. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Irvine, William. 2011. Editor’s Preface. In Musonius Rufus: Lectures & Sayings, ed. William Irvine, 9–12. Translated by Cynthia King. CreateSpace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, Evelyn. 1985. Reflections on Gender and Science. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, Janet. 2012. Feminist Critiques: Harding and Longino. In Philosophy of Science, ed. James Brown, 236–254. London and New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, Julia. 1980 (1977). Desire in Language: A Semiotic Approach to Literature and Art. Edited by Leon Roudiez. Translated by Thomas Gora, Alice Jardine, and Leon Roudiez. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. Women’s Time. Translated by Alice Jardine and Harry Blake. Signs 7 (1): 13–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1982. Psychoanalysis and the Polis. Translated by Margaret Waller. Critical Inquiry 9 (1): 77–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lampe, Kurt. 2016. Kristeva, Stoicism, and the “True Life of Interpretations”. SubStance 45 (1): 22–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LeGates, Marlene. 2001. In Their Time: A History of Feminism in Western Society. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Long, Anthony. 2002. Epictetus: A Stoic and Socratic Guide to Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Musonius Rufus. 2011. Musonius Rufus: Lectures & Sayings. Edited by William Irvine. Translated by Cynthia King. CreateSpace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 1994. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. The Incomplete Feminism of Musonius Rufus, Platonist, Stoic, and Roman. In The Sleep of Reason: Erotic Experience and Sexual Ethics in Ancient Greece and Rome, 283–326. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 2002. Apology. In Five Dialogues: Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Meno, Phaedo. Translated by George M.A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Republic. Translated by Christopher Rowe. London and New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reydams-Schils, Gretchen. 2005. The Roman Stoics: Self, Responsibility, and Affection. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. “Becoming like God” in Platonism and Stoicism. In From Stoicism to Platonism: The Development of Philosophy, 100 BCE–100 CE, ed. Troels Engberg-Pedersen, 142–158. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • UNESCO. 2013. Education for All Global Monitoring Reporting: Girls’ Education—The Facts. http://en.unesco.org/gem-report/sites/gem-report/files/girls-factsheet-en.pdf.

  • Weisberg, D. Kelly. 1977. Barred from the Bar: Women and Legal Education in the United States 1870–1890. Journal of Legal Education 28 (4): 485–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeandle, Heidi. 2017. Angela Carter and Western Philosophy. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Will Johncock .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Johncock, W. (2020). Can Education Be Egalitarian? Musonius Rufus and Julia Kristeva on Gendered Labor. In: Stoic Philosophy and Social Theory. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-43153-2_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics