Skip to main content

Idiocy and Irony

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
IDIOT LOVE and the Elements of Intimacy
  • 126 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter introduces the two central literary works to be discussed in the book: The Idiot (1869) by Fyodor Dostoevsky and Bad Love (2007) by French filmmaker Catherine Breillat. It lays out the reasoning for comparing these two works directly as two tragic love stories of mutual destruction–the later work having been directly influenced by the earlier one. Two additional core concepts in the book are then introduced and theorized: irony, which is conceived as a mental mechanism that brings conceptual tension to the fore, and idiocy, which is understood not in cognitive terms but in terms of interpersonal relations, as a lack of relational consciousness. This leads into a discussion of dialectical thinking as a moral imperative and also suggests that, from such a dialectical point of view, a book ostensibly about idiocy appears to also be about wisdom.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Fyodor Mikhailovich Dostoevsky (1989). All references to The Idiot refer to this edition and appear in my own translation.

  2. 2.

    Nina Pelikan-Straus (1998) claims that “Evgeny’s voice articulates a skeptical modern perspective…[a] mirror [that] shows Myshkin a naive but benignly ambitious young man who has read too many books” (122–123). She thus concludes that he “voices a dangerously modern clearance in the novel: a moment when the text’s official myth of Myshkin’s identity collapses and no laughter emerges” (124). Bruce A. French (2011), acknowledging that “Radomskij’s explanation has been called by Tunimanov the profoundest ‘worldly’ interpretation of Myskin and his interactions with other people,” still argues that “Radomskij’s way of looking at the prince’s actions and at this part of the novel is deficient” (51). Robin Feuer Miller has tended largely to agree with Evgeny Pavlovich’s position (1981).

  3. 3.

    Catherine Breillat (2007) 9. All references to the original French edition. English translation by Marie-Claire Merrigan and David Stromberg.

  4. 4.

    Breillat has been considered as an auteur of sex and the body, yet, as Sophie Bélot (2017) suggests in the very final words of her dedicated study: “Breillat’s cinema should be understood as intimate” (144). This last idea of her conclusion can be seen as an opening for the kind of analysis that will be undertaken in this study.

  5. 5.

    Jonathan Lear (2011) 9.

  6. 6.

    Wayne Booth (1974) 273.

  7. 7.

    These distinctions are split into two general approaches–attempts to qualify ‘Socratic irony’ as a complex speech-act in its own right, and attempts to read Socrates’s ironic speech-acts in a broader framework that includes the situational, dramatic, or structural elements of Plato’s dialogues. Gregory Vlastos (1987), who brought the first approach to focus, put forth a relatively straightforward claim: Socratic irony is a “complex irony [in which] what is said both is and isn’t what is meant” (86). A main criticism against the first position is that it fails to account for the dramatic elements of Plato’s works, locating the “source” of irony in Socrates as a character. Paula Gottlieb (1992), in her criticism of Vlastos, notes: “For the purposes of dramatic irony, Plato fully exploits the fact that Socratic irony amuses and pleases those in the know, while deceiving and angering those on the outside” (278). Jill Gordon (1996) strikes a similar note: “Vlastos’ notion of complex irony is not complex enough…because it fails to recognize the dramatic context in which Socratic irony is situated” (131).

  8. 8.

    Drew A. Hyland (1968) writes: “Plato was at least as much interested in [the] non-propositional aspect of philosophy as in the propositional side” (42); Hyland (1988) 326–327, 329–330, 335.

  9. 9.

    Hyland (1988) 327.

  10. 10.

    One strand of this debate can be traced to Charles L. Griswold (1986), who sets out an approach to differentiating between what Socrates says on the page and what Plato does, including the concept of Platonic irony. This led to a defense in Christopher Rowe (1987) for the possibility of taking Socrates’s words seriously. Dorit Cohn (2001) raised the debate again, suggesting that some of the voices in which Plato’s views may be found could be those that counter the voice of Socrates in the dialogues. And soon afterward, Griswold (2002) reiterated in greater detail his approach to Platonic irony and its relation to Socratic irony.

  11. 11.

    Plato (2008) 216e. Until this point in the Symposium , Socrates has, according to the accepted structure of the drinking party devoted to love, given a speech on love, a topic on which he says he is an expert–but, unlike the other characters, who present their own discourses on love, Socrates ‘reproduces’ a dialogue he held as a younger man with the priestess and wise woman, Diotima. Plato here portrays Socrates narrating a dialogue that took place between a younger self and an older teacher, just as Plato elsewhere portrays him speaking to others.

  12. 12.

    Plato (2000) 337a.

  13. 13.

    Plato (2000) 54n206.

  14. 14.

    Aristotle (2009) 4.7.14.

  15. 15.

    P. W. Gooch (1987) 95.

  16. 16.

    Richard Harvey Brown (1983). In Brown’s words, irony in Plato fuses “the author’s methods with…his critical reflection on his own interests and techniques” in a “dialectical revolving-back-upon-oneself” (546–547). He describes the emergence in the late Renaissance and early Romantic periods of three new understandings of irony–rhetorical irony, irony of action, and irony of events–wherein irony shifts from being understood as dissimulation to serving as a form of indirect communication. See also Paul R. Harrison (1994) 83.

  17. 17.

    Brown (1983) 544.

  18. 18.

    For Hegel (1892–1896), Socratic irony was a “mode of carrying on intercourse between one person and another”–a verbal speech-act that meant to help him derive the opposite of what was said.

  19. 19.

    Friedrich Schlegel (1971) 265.

  20. 20.

    Søren Kierkegaard (1989) 170.

  21. 21.

    Aristotle (2009) 4.7.9.

  22. 22.

    Talisse (2002) 50.

  23. 23.

    Talisse (2002) 52.

  24. 24.

    Gooch (1987) mentions Gregory Vlastos (1971) as a defense of “Socrates’ integrity” (102).

  25. 25.

    Plato (2000) 294.

  26. 26.

    Plato (2000) 295.

  27. 27.

    Plato (2000) 296.

  28. 28.

    As Matthew Landauer (2014) notes, Plato refers to this kind of idiotes in the Republic when “Socrates voices suspicion that those who desire to rule will invariably do it poorly” (146).

  29. 29.

    Talisse (2002) 52.

  30. 30.

    See especially Miller (1981) 63–65.

  31. 31.

    Frye (1957) 48–49.

  32. 32.

    As Val Vinokur (2008) puts it in his study of The Idiot: “For Dostoevsky…moral teaching comes less from another, from conversation, than somehow because of another…. Myshkin’s love of the beautiful prevents him from the justice…that ethics demands” (20–21).

  33. 33.

    Trudelle Thomas (2005) explains the psychosocial term as “refer[ring] to an awareness of our interdependence with other beings….It suggests a nuanced sensitivity to the complexity and connection of all creatures…[and] was popularized by David Hay in the 1990s through his research into the spirituality of English school children” (375).

  34. 34.

    See László F. Földényi (2004).

  35. 35.

    See Ludwig Wittgenstein (1922): “a proposition is true, if what we assert by means of it is the case; and if by ‘p’ we mean ∼p, and what we mean is the case, then ‘p’ in the new conception is true and not false” (43). In other words, if what we mean is the negation of a proposition, then that negation is the true case.

References

  • Aristotle. 2009 (c. 340 BC). The Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. David Ross and intr. Lesley Brown. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bélot, Sophie. 2017. The Cinema of Catherine Breillat. Leiden: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Booth, Wayne. 1974. A Rhetoric of Irony. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breillat, Catherine. 2007. Bad Love. Paris: Editions Léo Scheer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Richard Harvey. 1983. Dialectical Irony. Literary Form and Sociological Theory. Poetics Today 4 (3): 543–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohn, Dorit. 2001. Does Socrates Speak for Plato? Reflections on an Open Question. New Literary History 32 (3): 485–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dostoevsky, Fyodor Mikhailovich. 1989 (1869). Idiot: Roman v chetyrekh chastyakh. http://az.lib.ru/d/dostoewskij_f_m/text_0070.shtml. From Sobranie sochinenie b 15 tomakh, Tom 6. Leningrad: Nauka. Accessed 28 Nov 2019.

  • Földényi, László F. 2004. Dostoevsky Reads Hegel in Siberia and Bursts into Tears. Common Knowledge 10 (1): 93–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, Bruce A. 2011. Dostoevsky’s Idiot: Dialogue and the Spiritually Good Life. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frye, Northrop. 1957. Anatomy of Criticism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gooch, P.W. 1987. Socratic Irony and Aristotle’s ‘Eiron’: Some Puzzles. Phoenix 41 (2): 95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, Jill. 1996. Against Vlastos on Complex Irony. The Classical Quarterly 46 (1): 131–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb, Paula. 1992. The Complexity of Socratic Irony: A Note on Professor Vlastos’ Account. The Classical Quarterly 42: 278–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griswold, Charles L. 1986. Self-Knowledge in Plato’s Phaedrus. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Irony in the Platonic Dialogues. Philosophy and Literature 26 (1): 84–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, Paul R. 1994. The Disenchantment of Reason: The Problem of Socrates in Modernity. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 1892–1896 (1805–1806). Lectures on the History of Philosophy. Trans. E.S. Haldane. https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/hegel/works/hp/hpconten.htm. Accessed 16 Dec 2019.

  • Hyland, Drew A. 1968. Why Plato Wrote Dialogues. Philosophy & Rhetoric 1 (1): 38–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1988. Taking the longer road: The Irony of Plato’s ‘Republic’. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 93e.3: 317–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, Søren. 1989 (1841). The Concept of Irony, with Continual Reference to Socrates. In The Concept of Irony, with Continual Reference to Socrates: Together with Notes of Schelling’s Berlin Lectures, ed. and trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong, 1–332. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landauer, Matthew. 2014. The ‘Idiōtēs’ and the Tyrant: Two Faces of Unaccountability in Democratic Athens. Political Theory 42 (2): 139–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lear, Jonathan. 2011. A Case for Irony. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Robin Feuer. 1981. Dostoevsky and The Idiot: Author, Narrator, and Reader. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pelikan-Straus, Nina. 1998. Flights from The Idiot’s Womanhood. In Dostoevsky’s The Idiot: A Critical Companion, ed. Liza Knapp, 105–129. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 2000 (c. 375 BC). The Republic, ed. G.R.F. Ferrari and trans. Tom Griffith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008 (c. 385–370 BC). Symposium, ed. M.C. Howatson and Frisbee C.C. Sheffield and trans. M.C. Howatson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, Christopher. 1987. Platonic Irony. Inicio 5: 83–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlegel, Friedrich. 1971 (1800). On Incomprehensibility. In Friedrich Schlegel’s Lucinde and the Fragments, ed. Peter Firchow, 257–272. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talisse, Robert B. 2002. Misunderstanding Socrates. Arion: A Journal of Humanities and the Classics 9 (3): 46–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, Trudelle. 2005. Relational Consciousness. In Encyclopedia of Religious and Spiritual Development, ed. Elizabeth M. Dowling and W. Goerge Scarlett, 375–377. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vinokur, Val. 2008. Idiots and Demons: Dostoevsky’s Aesthetic Perils. In The Trace of Judaism: Dostoevsky, Babel, Mandelstam, Levinas. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vlastos, Gregory. 1971. The Paradox of Socrates. In Critical Essays, 1–21. Garden City: Doubleday & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. Socratic Irony. The Classical Quarterly 37 (1): 79–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, intr. Bertrand Russell. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Stromberg, D. (2020). Idiocy and Irony. In: IDIOT LOVE and the Elements of Intimacy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-42695-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics