Skip to main content

VII Moral Elegance: An Ethics Tailored to Vanity Fairs?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Vanity Fairs
  • 368 Accesses

Abstract

Vanity fairs are the most successful market form of the 21st century economy. They represent the market form that the industrial base of knowledge society and the business models of the most prosperous firms of the present-day economy rely on. The success, however, comes at a price. Competitions for attention, incomparable in mobilizing creative and cognitive efforts, are incomparable also in exposing the tender flesh of our innermost selves to the cunning of business acumen .

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The classic reference to this ordinal utility theory, as it is called, is de Graaff (1957).

  2. 2.

    The paradigm case of complementarity is the wave-particle dualism in quantum theory . Wave and particle are incompatible properties of an entity, but both are necessary for an encompassing description of quantum objects. Complementarity, thus conceived, was introduced by Nils Bohr , who in turn was inspired by a psychological notion thereof that ultimately goes back to William James . On the re-introduction of the concept of complementarity into psychology see Wang and Busemeyer (2015).

  3. 3.

    cf. Franck 2010

  4. 4.

    For a scientific account of this basic ambivalence of the human condition see Kauffman (2008).

  5. 5.

    This is not to say, however, that it is hard to show that deliberate agnosticism has a dehumanizing effect. The effect is demonstrated brutally by a worldview pervasive in our science -minded civilization. The view consists in the seemingly innocent definition of nature as that which natural science describes. The identification of nature with the scope of natural science is known as naturalism . Since sentience has no place in the scope of natural science, this definition of nature amounts to banning sentient nature from nature proper. Deliberative ignorance of sentience may seem arguable on the grounds of the inaccessibility of sentience by empirical method. Basic research and pure theory alike deserve to be shielded against issues they are not equipped to answer. As long as basic research serves exclusively cognitive interests, it arguably can refuse social responsibility for its outcome. Things change when the outcome of knowledge production transcends the province of pure theory. As soon as naturalism turns into a quasi-official worldview of technologically advanced societies, denial of sentient nature means to give the blessing to ruthless brutality toward animals on industrial scale. How dehumanizing deliberate ignorance can be is demonstrated by the cruelty to animals inherent in intensive farming and the unscrupulous processing of sensitive tissue in the meat and fish industries. Dismissing natural spirituality is much more than just shortsightedness. It is a serious threat to the nature we are part of ourselves. Loosening the blindfold is an ethical command far exceeding the domain of vanity fairs.

References

  • Aristotle. 2011. The Eudemian Ethics, trans. Anthony Kenny, Oxford: Oxford World’s Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Confucius. 2009. The Confucian Analects, the Great Learning & the Doctrine of the Mean, trans. James Legge, New York: Cosimo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1974. On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme: Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graaff, J. de V. 1957. Theoretical Welfare Economics. London: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, Paul H. 1975. Logic and Conversation. In Syntax and Semantics, vol. 3, Speech Acts, ed. Peter Cole, and Jerry L. Morgan, 41–58. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, Stuart. 2008. Reinventing the Sacred: A New View of Science, Reason, and Religion. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, John Henry. 1852–9. The Idea of a University. London. Reprint Dublin: Ashfield, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peil Kauffman, Katherine T. 2012. Emotion: A Self-Regulatory Sense? FTS International. Available at www.emotionalsentience.com).

  • Wang, Zheng, and Jerome Busemeyer. 2015. Reintroducing the Concept of Complementarity Into Psychology. In Frontiers in Psychology, vol. 6 (Nov 2015), article 1822 (www.frontiersin.org).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Georg Franck .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Franck, G. (2020). VII Moral Elegance: An Ethics Tailored to Vanity Fairs?. In: Vanity Fairs. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-41532-7_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics