Skip to main content

The Scope and Power of Abstraction in Science

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 422))

Abstract

In the present paper, I argue that at least some models are abstract entities and hence that at least some of the content of scientific theories is abstract. I further argue that abstraction, which is ubiquitous in science, is the vehicle for the discovery and representation of abstract objects. Finally, I argue against taking models to be fictions. In Sect. 9.2, I present in some detail the case of the Carnot Engine as a typical case of a model in science and defend the view that it is best seen as a real but abstract entity. In Sect. 9.3, I distinguish and discuss three modes of abstraction in science, which I call Aristotelian, Newtonian and Duhemian. In Sect. 9.4, I offer reasons to resist fictionalism about models. I discuss Kendall Walton’s pretence theory of representation and I argue against extending it to the case of scientific models. I show that the current neo-fictionalist account of models fails and that considering models as real but abstract entities is a better account of models than neo-fictionalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “Two classes have the same number when, and only when, there is a one-one relation whose domain includes the one class, and which is such that the class of correlates of the terms of the one class is identical with the other class” (1903, 113).

  2. 2.

    In Grundlagen, he showed the power of abstraction principles by introducing the concept of direction over the equivalence relation ‘being a parallel line to’ (1884, 74–78; §63–67).

    • (D=) The direction of the line a is the same as the direction of the line b if, and only if a is parallel to b.

    • or,

    • (D=) D(a) = D(b) iff a//b.

    For Frege, lines are given in (spatial) intuition and yet directions (introduced as above) are abstract entities not given in intuition. The concept of direction is discovered by a process of intellectual activity which takes its start from intuition. For Frege abstraction principles explain our capacity to refer to abstract objects. ‘The direction of the line a’ is a singular term; it refers to an object. (D=) enables us to identify this object as the same again (criterion of identity) under a different description, e.g., ‘The direction of the line b’. We thereby have a criterion of identity: the criterion of identity of the new entities S (e.g., directions) is given in terms of a relation R (which is an equivalence relation) on things of some other kind G (e.g., parallel lines).

  3. 3.

    For a succinct but informative account of abstraction principles see Horsten and Leitgeb (2009).

  4. 4.

    For more discussion of the transfictional statements, see Peter Godfrey-Smith (2009).

References

  • Aristotle. (1991). Metaphysics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), Complete works. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bäck, A. (2014). Aristotle’s theory of abstraction. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carnot, S. (1824). Reflections on the motive power of fire: And other papers on the second law of thermodynamics. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clapeyron, E. (1834). Mémoire sur la Puissance Motrice de la Chaleur. Journal de l’Ecole Royale Polytechnique, XIV, 153–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1892). Some reflections on the subject of physical theories. In Essays in the history and philosophy of science (R. Ariew and P. Barker, Trans. and ed., pp. 1–28). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1893). The English school and physical theories. In Essays in the history and philosophy of science (R. Ariew and P. Barker, Trans. and ed., pp. 50–74). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forster, E. M. (1962). In O. Stallybrass (Ed.), Aspects of the novel. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884). The foundations of arithmetic (J. L. Austin Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010a). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172, 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010b). Fiction and scientific representation. In R. Frigg & M. Hunter (Eds.), Beyond mimesis and convention. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Models and fictions in science. Philosophical Studies, 143, 101–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horsten, L., & Leitgeb, H. (2009). How abstraction works. In A. Hieke & H. Leitgeb (Eds.), Reduction – Abstraction – Analysis (pp. 217–226). Frankfurt: Ontos Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mally, E. (1912). Gegenstandstheoretische Grundlagen der Logik und Logistik. Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1729). The mathematical principles of natural philosophy (A. Motte Trans.). Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1934.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2010). Scientific realism: Between Platonism and nominalism. Philosophy of Science, 77, 947–958.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2011). Living with the abstract: Realism and models. Synthese, 190, 3–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1903). Principles of mathematics. Abingdon: Routledge (2009).

    Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2012). Models as make-believe. Imagination, fiction and scientific representation. Palgrave-MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (n.d.). Models as make-believe. In R. Frigg & M. Hunter (Eds.), Beyond mimesis and convention. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaihinger, H. (1911). The philosophy of ‘As If’ (C. K. Ogden, Trans.). London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co Ltd (1935).

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, J. (2011). Modern thermodynamics. Based on the extended Carnot theorem. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (1983). Abstract objects: An introduction to axiomatic metaphysics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the workshop “Scientific Contents: Fictions or Abstract Objects?”, organized by the EPISTEME Research Group, at the University of Santiago de Compostela, in January 2017. Many thanks to Xavier de Donato and José L. Falguera for their kind invitation and to the participants for useful comments and questions. Thanks are due to an anonymous reader and the editors of this volume for their patience and support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stathis Psillos .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Psillos, S. (2020). The Scope and Power of Abstraction in Science. In: Falguera, J.L., Martínez-Vidal, C. (eds) Abstract Objects. Synthese Library, vol 422. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-38242-1_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics