Skip to main content

Models and Denotation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 422))

Abstract

Many models function representationally. Considerable differences notwithstanding, most accounts of representation involve the notion that models denote their targets. Denotation is a dyadic relation that obtains between certain symbols and certain objects. This does not sit well with the fact that many models are not concrete objects. If a model does not exist, how can it denote? We present an antirealist theory of models that reconciles the notion that models don’t exist with the claim that there is real denotation between models and their targets.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Or reference – in the philosophy of language the terms “denotation” and “reference” are often used as synonyms.

  2. 2.

    Kaplan’s (1990) investigation into the nature of words (and proper names in particular) as the media of denotation is a noteworthy exception.

  3. 3.

    Fiction accounts of models have also been advocated by Barberousse and Ludwig (2009), Frigg (2010), Frigg and Nguyen (2016), Giere (2010, 278) (although he stresses that this is restricted to ontology, functionally models and fictions might come apart), Salis (2019) and Salis and Frigg (2020). Levy (2015) and Toon (2012) present accounts that appeal to fiction, but are designed in way that does not require that a model denote a target. For a discussion of their account see Frigg and Ngueyn (2017, 86–88).

  4. 4.

    The objection actually applies more generally: anyone who thinks that models are not concrete objects but denote their targets will face the same challenge.

  5. 5.

    See, for instance, Frigg (2010), Levy (2015), and Toon (2012).

  6. 6.

    See Opie and Opie (1969) for a description of this game.

  7. 7.

    Walton assumes referentialism, the position that utterances of sentences containing proper names express singular propositions. For instance, the proposition “Saint Paul’s Cathedral is Northern Europe’s biggest church” is directly about St Paul’s in virtue of having St Paul’s among its constituents. This view entails that utterances of sentences containing fictional names (names without referents) express either no proposition or a gappy proposition. Walton (1990, Ch. 10) assumes the former and argues that utterances of sentences containing fictional names are to be analysed in terms of kinds of pretence. Friend (2011) and Salis (2013) emphasise that this is insufficient to distinguish different kinds of pretence that seem to be about different fictional objects. They offer alternative analyses in terms of gappy propositions and participation in different networks of information (Friend 2011) and different name-using practices (Salis 2013).

  8. 8.

    In fact, Weisberg (2007) identifies the existence of a secondary object that does the representing as a defining feature of modelling.

  9. 9.

    In the late1960s philosophers of mind and language introduced the notion of a mental file as a cognitive representation of concrete objects as individuals rather than as the possessors of properties. Originally, Grice (1969, 141–142) introduced this notion under the label “dossier” in his discussion of vacuous names and referentially used descriptions. The idea is that our thoughts latch onto reality in a direct way, i.e. through a perceptual relation with individual objects rather than through the mediation of a descriptive condition that looks for the object as the satisfier of a certain set of qualitative features. In line with this idea, Perry (1980) introduced the term “mental file” to account for the phenomenon of continued belief and he appealed to the same notion to account for the phenomenon of co-reference in his (2001, 128–146). Bach (1987, Ch. 3, spec. 34–39, 44) deployed mental files in his discussion of de re thought. More recently, Jeshion (2010) presented a new theory of singular thought as thought from mental files. Friend (2011, 2014) appeals to mental files to explain the phenomenon of intersubjective identification of fictional characters within fictional antirealism. Intersubjective identification of the same object, or co-identification, is further explained in terms of participation in the same information network (Friend 2011, 2014) or the same name-using practice (Salis 2013) supporting the mental files. Linguists have used the notion of a mental file as discourse referents (Heim 1982; Kamp and Reyle 1993; Karttunen 1976). Cognitive psychologists have introduced the analogous notions of object files to study visual representations in adults’ object-directed attention (Pylyshyn 2000, 2001, 2007; Fodor and Pylyshyn 2014) and object concepts to theorise about object representations in infancy (Spelke 1990; Baillargeon 1995; Carey 2009). Pylyshyn (2001, 129) draws an explicit connection between the philosophical literature on mental files and the notion of object files to emphasize the purely causal relation between object files and their referents. Philosophers Murez and Recanati (2016) make some important distinctions between Pylyshyn’s notion of object files and mental files by underlying the conceptual nature of the latter. They emphasise that mental files can store qualitative information about their objects (and in this sense they can be construed as conceptual representations of individual objects). However, this qualitative information is not used to fix the referent of the mental file. Information can be updated, retrieved and deleted without changing the referent of the file. It is in this sense that we say that mental files represent concrete objects as individuals rather than as the possessors of properties. Perner et al. (2015) explicitly appeal to mental files to develop a cognitive theory of belief representation in infancy.

  10. 10.

    This happens, for instance, when a file involves an expression that appears to be a proper name. The head of department says “room 425 is too small to host the admin office”. A singular term like “Room 425” has its own individual mental file, and so does each item described in the dossier. In fact, there can be a hierarchy of files. But the files contain only information (predicates) about the objects. They don’t contain singular terms. They are cognitive representations in the mind that stand for objects in reality, if there are any. They are associated with singular terms without including them.

  11. 11.

    Fregean senses are usually interpreted as descriptive modes of presentation of objects, i.e. descriptive conditions such as “the morning star”, that are parts of the propositional content of thoughts. For example, the content of the thought that “Phosphorus will rise in the morning” will be that the morning star will rise in the morning. Mental files, however, are not necessarily interpreted as descriptive modes of presentation that enter into the propositional content of thoughts. See, e.g., Recanati (2012) for a critical discussion of the relation between mental files and descriptivism.

  12. 12.

    In this section we use “pretend” and “imagine” in their non-technical sense, which is broader than the technical sense introduced in Sect. 10.2.

  13. 13.

    See Slutkin’s (2016). Thanks to David Kinney for telling us about this case.

  14. 14.

    It’s worth noting here that we take the model’s representational content to be the result of imputing the Q 1, …, Q m to T. this representational content is distinct from the model-content itself in so far as the latter concerns claims about target systems whereas the former concern claims about, or pretend about, the model systems themselves.

  15. 15.

    A difference is that G becomes obsolete in concrete models because the material object itself generates the model truths. When using the Phillips-Newlyn machine, we don’t use principles of generation to find out how the economy behaves; we let the machine run!

References

  • Bach, K. (1987). Thought and reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R. (1995). Physical reasoning in infancy. In M. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive neurosciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberousse, A., & Ludwig, P. (2009). Models as fictions. In M. Suárez (Ed.), Fictions in science: Philosophical essays on modeling and idealization (pp. 56–73). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, T. W., & Halvorson, H. (2016). Glymour and quine on theoretical equivalence. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 45(5), 467–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origion of concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Contessa, G. (2007). Scientific representation, interpretation, and surrogative reasoning. Philosophy of Science, 74(1), 48–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. Z. (2010). Telling instances. In R. Frigg & M. C. Hunter (Eds.), Beyond mimesis and convention: Representation in art and science (pp. 1–18). Berlin/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. Z. (2017). True enough. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (2014). Minds without meanings: An essay on the content of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (1999). Reinflating the semantic approach. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13, 103–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friend, S. (2011). The great beetle debate. Philosophical Studies, 153(183–211), 183–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friend, S. (2014). Notions of nothing. In M. García-Carpintero & G. Martí (Eds.), Empty representations: Reference and non-existence (pp. 307–332). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172(2), 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2016). The fiction view of models reloaded. The Monist, 99, 225–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2017). Models and representation. In L. Magnani & T. Bertolotti (Eds.), Springer handbook of model-based science (pp. 49–102). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2018). The turn of the valve: Representing with material models. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8(2), 205–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2010). An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese, 172(1), 269–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (1971). Theoretical realism and theoretical equivalence. In R. C. Buck, R. Carnap, & R. Cohen (Eds.), Proceeding of the 1970 biennial meeting philosophy of science association (pp. 275–288). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy, 21(5), 725–740.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1969). Vacuous names. In D. Davidson & J. Hintikka (Eds.), Words and objections (pp. 118–145). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Halvorson, H. (2012). What scientific theories could not be. Philosophy of Science, 79(2), 183–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1982). The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Amherst: University of Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendry, R. F., & Psillos, S. (2007). How to do things with theories: An interactive view of language and models in science. In J. Brzeziński, A. Klawiter, T. A. F. Kuipers, K. Łastowski, K. Paprzycka, & P. Przybysz (Eds.), The courage of doing philosophy: Essays dedicated to Leszek Nowak (pp. 123–157). New York: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeshion, R. (2010). Singular thought: Acquaintance, semantic instrumentalism and cognitivism. In R. Jeshion (Ed.), New essays on singular thought (pp. 105–140). Oxford: Calarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From discourse to logic: Introduction to modeltheoretic semantics of natural language, formal logic and discourse representation theory (Studies in linguistics and philosophy) (Vol. 42). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1990). Words. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 1(64), 93–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L. (1976). Discourse referents. In J. McCawley (Ed.), Notes from the linguistic underground (Syntax and semantics) (Vol. 7, pp. 363–385).

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2015). Modeling without models. Philosophical Studies, 152(3), 781–798.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murez, M., & Recanati, F. (2016). Mental files: An introduction. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 7, 265–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Opie, I., & Opie, P. (1969). Children’s games in street and playground. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., Huemer, M., & Leahy, B. (2015). Mental files and belief: A cognitive theory of how children represent belief and its intensionality. Cognition, 145, 77–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1980). A problem about continued belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 61, 317–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Reference and reflexivity. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2000). Situating vision in the world. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4, 197–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2001). Visual indexes, preconceptual objects, and situated vision. Cognition, 80, 127–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2007). Things and places: How the mind connects with the world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1975). On empirically equivalent systems of the world. Erkenntnis, 9, 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2012). Mental files. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salis, F. (2013). Fictional names and the problem of intersubjective identification. Dialectica, 67(3), 283–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salis, F. (2020). Capturing the Scientific Imagination, in P. Godfrey-Smith & A. Levy (Eds.), The Scientific Imagination (pp. 17–50). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salis, F., & Frigg, R. (2020). Capturing the scientific imagination. In P. Godfrey-Smith & A. Levy (Eds.), The scientific imagination (pp. 17–50). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slutkin, G. (2016). Is violence ‘senseless’? Not according to science. Let’s make sense of it and treat it like a disease. Health Progress, 97(4), 5–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. (1990). Principles of object perception. Cognitive Science, 14, 29–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (2000). Theory identity. In W. H. Newton-Smith (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 525–527). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2010). Missing systems and face value practise. Synthese, 172(2), 283–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2012). Modeling without mathematics. Philosophy of Science, 79(5), 761–772.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toon, A. (2012). Models as make-believe. Imagination, fiction and scientific representation. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Who is a modeler? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, 207–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1984). An unreal image. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34(1), 65–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roman Frigg .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Salis, F., Frigg, R., Nguyen, J. (2020). Models and Denotation. In: Falguera, J.L., Martínez-Vidal, C. (eds) Abstract Objects. Synthese Library, vol 422. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-38242-1_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics