Skip to main content

Good Reasons and Natural Ends: Rosalind Hursthouse’s Hermeneutical Naturalism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Aristotelian Naturalism

Part of the book series: Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action ((HSNA,volume 8))

Abstract

Rosalind Hursthouse (∗1943) is known chiefly both for her groundbreaking work in applying virtue ethics to practical matters and for her 1999 monograph On Virtue Ethics, which represents one of the first and few systematic treatments of modern virtue ethics and, in its central doctrines, remains highly influential to this day. The third and final part of this book is devoted to what is now known as neo-Aristotelian ethical naturalism, which in Hursthouse’s own words generally consists in “the enterprise of basing ethics in some way on considerations of human nature” (192). On her account, this project specifically aims at rendering the rationality of virtuous action intelligible by situating it in the wider context of human life.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Unless otherwise noted, all references are to Hursthouse (1999). Another comparably systematic development of modern virtue ethics, which appeared around the same time, is Müller (1998). For some of Hursthouse’s important contributions to applied ethics, cf. Hursthouse (1987, 1991, 1995, 2000, 2006, 2009, 2011).

  2. 2.

    Throughout this paper, I will use ‘practical thought’ and ‘ethical thought’ more or less interchangeably to refer to thought about what ought to be done.

  3. 3.

    This misunderstanding underlies a widespread line of criticism against neo-Aristotelian naturalism, which seeks to demonstrate that the traditional virtues are incompatible with, and therefore cannot be grounded in, a purely evolutionary or biological account of human beings. Cf. Andreou (2006), Millum (2006), and Millgram (2009). As will become apparent by the end of this paper, a similar misunderstanding also underlies Leist’s (2010, 136-141) charge that Hursthouse’s ‘biological’ naturalism fails due to its alleged reliance on an outdated vitalistic folk biology that has been refuted by post-Darwinian scientific biology.

  4. 4.

    Cf. Thompson (2004) and Hacker-Wright (2009) for comparable approaches.

  5. 5.

    Rehg and Davis (2003) argue that, since Hursthouse does not embrace a scientistic concept of nature, her virtue ethics cannot count as genuinely naturalistic either. Yet, if ‘naturalism’ merely means the attempt at providing an explanation, validation, or justification in terms of nature, then it leaves open which concept of nature to employ. It seems that, in principle, nothing precludes a normative concept of nature from doing this work. Rehg and Davis deny this by pointing out structural analogies between Hursthouse’s normative concept of human nature and a decidedly non-naturalistic Neo-Kantian concept of normativity. One may wonder, however, whether Rehg and Davis sufficiently heed the differences between these views and whether they do not, from the outset, formulate their criteria for a genuinely naturalistic concept of nature with scientism firmly in mind.

  6. 6.

    But note that critics such as Hare (1957), Pigden (1990), and Halbig (2015, 180–182) have questioned whether we do in fact employ ‘good’ consistently in a logically attributive manner. While I believe we do, on a proper understanding of logical attributiveness, I cannot argue the matter here for reasons of space.

  7. 7.

    Halbig (2015), 184–186, argues that the exclusion of health aspects from the overall evaluation of human beings represents a significant breach of continuity to other living beings, and that this seriously imperils the naturalistic character of ethical evaluation on Hursthouse’s account. It is important to note, however, that even among the other living beings there are significant differences regarding their aspects and natural ends. Clearly then, Hursthouse understands the continuity between the structures of evaluation that form part of different biological species concepts or natures not in terms of strict identity but rather in terms of family resemblance. Yet, speaking with McDowell, this allows for a ‘relaxed naturalism’ that is open to an essentially ethical form of evaluating living beings and a normative concept of human nature as essentially second nature.

  8. 8.

    Lott (2014) offers a systematic discussion of this objection as raised against neo-Aristotelian naturalism more generally.

  9. 9.

    A variant of the foundationalist picture also underlies Gowans’ (2008) charge that a “straightforward application of the Teleological Criterion” (52) allegedly formed by the four ends will not yield anything resembling our morality, and that in particular moral universalism cannot be derived from it. That is, Gowans treats the four ends as a criterion that we can apply to test ethical beliefs directly. Yet, this is not Hursthouse’s intent. Although the four ends are meant to guide ethical thought and argument somehow, they are not meant to effectively replace it with a quasi-technical decision procedure of this kind.

  10. 10.

    Cf. Müller (1992) for a discussion of this essentially ‘unreasoned’ teleology.

  11. 11.

    For ‘hinge propositions’, cf. Wittgenstein (1974), §§341–343, and Schönbaumsfeld (2016). In her attempt at uncovering the logical grammar of ethical thought, Hursthouse (208–211; 2004, 269–271) not only argues that the reasons of virtue in fact reflect these four ends, but also that other ethical theories contain traces of them. In line with Wittgenstein’s therapeutic conception of philosophy, these theories are thereby shown to be one-sided or otherwise defective explications of our actual practice, which ultimately threaten to corrupt it.

  12. 12.

    Cf. Hacker-Wright (2013) for a similar interpretation of the four ends. For a critical perspective, cf. Brüllmann (2013).

References

  • Andreou, C. (2006). Getting on in a varied world. Social Theory and Practice, 32(1), 61–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (2005). Virtue ethics: What kind of naturalism? In S. Gardiner (Ed.), Virtue ethics, old and new (pp. 11–29). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brüllmann, P. (2013). Good (as) human beings. In J. Peters (Ed.), Aristotelian ethics in contemporary perspective (pp. 97–113). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D., & Sobel, D. (2004). Morality and virtue. An assessment of some recent work in virtue ethics. Ethics, 114(3), 514–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. (1956). Good and evil. Analysis, 17(2), 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gowans, C. (2008). Virtue and nature. Social Philosophy and Policy, 25(1), 28–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright, J. (2009). What is natural about Foot’s ethical naturalism? Ratio, 22(3), 308–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacker-Wright, J. (2013). Human nature, virtue, and rationality. In J. Peters (Ed.), Aristotelian ethics in contemporary perspective (pp. 83–96). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halbig, C. (2015). Ein Neustart der Ethik? Zur Kritik des aristotelischen Naturalismus. In M. Rothhaar & M. Hähnel (Eds.), Normativität des Lebens – Normativität der Vernunft? (pp. 175–197). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. (1957). Geach: Good and evil. Analysis, 17(5), 103–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1987). Beginning lives. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1991). Virtue theory and abortion. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 20(3), 223–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1995). Applying virtue ethics. In R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, & W. Quinn (Eds.), Virtues and reasons. Philippa Foot and moral theory (pp. 57–75). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1999). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2000). Ethics, humans and other animals. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2002). Virtue ethics vs. rule-consequentialism: A reply to Brad hooker. Utilitas, 14(1), 41–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2004). On the grounding of the virtues in human nature. In J. Szaif & M. Lutz-Bachmann (Eds.), Was ist das für den Menschen Gute? Menschliche Natur und Güterlehre/What is Good for a Human Being? Human Nature and Values (pp. 263–275). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2006). Applying virtue ethics to our treatment of the other animals. In J. Welchman (Ed.), The practice of virtue. Classic and contemporary readings in virtue ethics (pp. 136–155). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2009). Environmental virtue ethics. In R. Walker & P. Ivanhoe (Eds.), Working virtue: Virtue ethics and contemporary moral problems (pp. 155–172). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2011). Virtue ethics and the treatment of animals. In T. Beauchamp & R. G. Frey (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of animal ethics (pp. 119–143). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2012). Human nature and Aristotelian virtue ethics. In C. Sandis & M. J. Cain (Eds.), Human nature (Royal Institute of Philosophy supplement) (Vol. 70, pp. 169–188). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leist, A. (2010). Wie moralisch ist unsere menschliche Natur? Naturalismus bei Foot und Hursthouse. In T. Hoffmann & M. Reuter (Eds.), Natürlich gut. Aufsätze zur Philosophie von Philippa Foot (pp. 121–148). Frankfurt am Main: Ontos.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lemos, J. (2007). Foot and Aristotle on virtues and flourishing. Philosophia, 35(1), 43–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lott, M. (2014). Why be a good human being? Natural goodness, reason, and the authority of human nature. Philosophia, 42(3), 761–777.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1995). Two sorts of naturalism. In R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, & W. Quinn (Eds.), Virtues and reasons. Philippa Foot and moral theory (pp. 149–179). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millgram, E. (2009). Life and action. Analysis, 69(3), 557–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millum, J. (2006). Natural goodness and natural evil. Ratio, 19(2), 199–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, A. W. (1992). Mental teleology. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 92, 161–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, A. W. (1998). Was taugt die Tugend? Elemente einer Ethik des guten Lebens. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigden, C. (1990). Geach on good. The Philosophical Quarterly, 40(159), 129–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rehg, W., & Davis, D. (2003). Conceptual gerrymandering? The alignment of hursthouse’s naturalistic virtue ethics with neo-kantian non-naturalism. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 41(4), 583–600.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schönbaumsfeld, G. (2016). ‘Hinge propositions’ and the ‘logical’ exclusion of doubt. International Journal for the Study of Skepticism, 6(2–3), 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2004). Apprehending human form. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Modern moral philosophy (Royal Institute of Philosophy supplement) (Vol. 54, pp. 47–74). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1995). Evolution, ethics, and the representation problem. In Making sense of humanity (pp. 100–110). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Über Gewissheit. On Certainty [1969]. (Ed. by G. E. M. Anscombe, G. H. von Wright. Corr. Ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sascha Settegast .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Settegast, S. (2020). Good Reasons and Natural Ends: Rosalind Hursthouse’s Hermeneutical Naturalism. In: Hähnel, M. (eds) Aristotelian Naturalism. Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action, vol 8. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-37576-8_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics