Skip to main content

Affective Nihilists, Weak Agents

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 319 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I explain that for Nietzsche, affective nihilism (as a drive-based, psychophysiological disorder) is a problem of weakened agency. Otherwise put, affective nihilists are weak agents, though Nietzsche offers different version of this will-weakness: either the intensity of one’s will is diminished due to the weakened activity of one’s drives, or the efficacy and endurance of one’s will drops off as one’s will is fragmented into a chaotic cluster of contradictory drives.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Creasy, Kaitlyn. 2019. “Making Knowledge the Most Powerful Affect: Overcoming Affective Nihilism.” Journal of Nietzsche Studies 50 (2): 210–232.

  2. 2.

    Importantly, however, describing affective nihilism as a problem of weakened agency that can be explained as a psychophysiological disorder does not tell the whole story of affective nihilism and its significance for Nietzsche. Indeed, as mentioned in the previous chapter, it is critical for Nietzsche that affective nihilism as a disorder can be caused by the internalization of life-denying norms or beliefs: norms and beliefs inherited from one’s culture or society.

  3. 3.

    This view is also shared by Gemes (2009, p. 42).

  4. 4.

    For more on this, see Huddleston (2019b, pp. 86–87).

  5. 5.

    Katsafanas (2016) argues that agential unity does not result when “one drive predominates and coordinates the other drives” (2016, p. 175). Instead, he believes that “an agent is unified—or, equivalently, the agent is active in the production of her action—when she approves of her action, and further knowledge of the action’s etiology would not undermine the approval” (ibid., p. 195). This is because Katsafanas, unlike other scholars (Gemes 2009; Richardson 2009), understands unity to involve a “relation between [one’s] drives and [one’s] conscious thoughts” (ibid., p. 165). Such unity is required for one to be a genuine agent. On Katsafanas’ view, however, it seems that the last man may very well count as a unified agent, one who genuinely acts as opposed to one who merely manifests behaviors in virtue of his drives. After all, the last man experiences an unreflective, easy contentedness with the ends he pursues—that is to say, he seems to approve of his ends and actions—and his noncommittal, detached attitude makes it unlikely that discovering the etiology of his actions (what seems to be a desire for undisturbed, simple comfort) would trouble him at all. In fact, that “sunny and impartial hospitality with which he accepts everything that comes his way, his type of unscrupulous benevolence” (BGE 207) seems to ensure that he would remain cheerful and unmoved even in the face of such a discovery. Yet Nietzsche characterizes the last man’s will as lacking unity. According to Nietzsche,  the last man’s soul undergoes “ever greater deterioration and disintegration” (KSA 11:25[9]; he has “no goal, no conclusion and sunrise […] nothing tough, powerful, self-reliant that wants to be master” (BGE 207). (Note here that I read Nietzsche’s descriptions of the last man, the theoretical man, and the objective man as descriptions of the same type of individual.) Thus, I resist Katsafanas’s claim that Nietzschean unity involves a relation between conscious thought and drives (rather than a relation among one’s drives and affects). In addition, it seems clear that Nietzsche would not characterize the last man as an agent. Indeed, the last man’s behaviors and pursuits are framed as mere “pastimes” (Z P:5); according to Nietzsche, such a man “change[s], [he does] not become” (KSA 13:14[157]). Thus, the particular kind of self-approbation described by Katsafanas—one that would persist in the face of discoveries about the origins of one’s actions—is not a sufficient condition for agency in Nietzsche. Still, I do think that Nietzsche believes a kind of self-approbatory attitude similar to the one Katsafanas describes here will be an important characteristic of one who has overcome affective nihilism: this will be the attitude that “redeem[s] what is past…. transform[ing] every ‘It was’ into ‘Thus I willed it’” (Z II:20). I discuss this at more length in the eighth chapter.

  6. 6.

    Socrates’ development of “a hypertrophy of the logical faculty” as a response to his spirit’s anarchy is no indication that he has unified his will in the way Nietzsche recommends; indeed, in Socrates’ case, reason plays the role of “counter-tyrant” (TI, “Socrates,” 9) to the drives, which Socrates already experiences as tyrannical. One whose will is unified in the proper way will achieve mastery over their drives in the form of their dominant drive or set of drives; the dominant drives do not become a “tyrant” in Nietzsche’s healthy individual. For more on this distinction between tyranny and mastery, see Reginster (2003) and Katsafanas (2016).

  7. 7.

    Further support for this point can be found in a note from the Nachlass in which Nietzsche characterizes “objectivity as the disintegration of the will [Willens-Disgregation]” (KSA 13:14[83]).

  8. 8.

    It is worth noting that the connection between mechanical activity and the herd instinct appears in both Zarathustra and the Genealogy.

  9. 9.

    Although a robust account of Nietzschean nihilism must include affective nihilism, it is not the case that every Nietzschean nihilist suffers from affective nihilism. Indeed, one can judge this-worldly existence negatively or believe in the worthlessness of existence without suffering from affective nihilism.

  10. 10.

    Importantly, though it is a necessary condition of overcoming affective nihilism that one’s will is strengthened and one is able to accomplish those goals one sets for oneself, this is not sufficient for overcoming nihilism (Anderson 2013, p. 164). This is something I discuss at greater length in the next two chapters.

References

  • Anderson, R. Lanier. 2013. “Love and the Moral Psychology of the Hegelian Nietzsche: Comments on Robert Pippin’s Nietzsche, Psychology, and First Philosophy.” The Journal of Nietzsche Studies 44 (2): 158–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gemes, Ken. 2008. “A Review of and Dialogue with Bernard Reginster.” The European Journal of Philosophy 16 (3): 459–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gemes, Ken. 2009. “Nietzsche on Free Will, Autonomy, and the Sovereign Individual.” In Nietzsche on Freedom and Autonomy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gemes, Ken, and Christopher Sykes. 2013. “Nihilism.” In Encyclopedia of Philosophy and the Social Sciences. Edited by B. Kaldis. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huddleston, Andrew. 2019a. Nietzsche on the Decadence and Flourishing of Culture. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huddleston, Andrew. 2019b. “Nietzsche on Nihilism: A Unifying Thread.” Philosophers’ Imprint 19 (11): 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katsafanas, Paul. 2016. The Nietzschean Self. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2002. Beyond Good and Evil. Translated by Judith Norman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1967. The Case of Wagner. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1974. The Gay Science. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2005. Nietzsche: The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols, And Other Writings. Translated by Judith Norman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2007. On the Genealogy of Morality. Translated by Carol Diethe. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1967–77. Sämtliche Werke, Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 Bänden. Edited by G. Colli and M. Montinari. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2006. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Translated by Adrian Del Caro. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reginster, Bernard. 2006. The Affirmation of Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reginster, Bernard. 2003. “What Is a Free Spirit? Nietzsche on Fanaticism.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 85: 51–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, John. 2009. “Nietzsche’s Freedoms.” In Nietzsche on Freedom and Autonomy. Edited by Ken Gemes and Simon May. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kaitlyn Creasy .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Creasy, K. (2020). Affective Nihilists, Weak Agents. In: The Problem of Affective Nihilism in Nietzsche. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-37133-3_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics