Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Active Cognition

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 23))

  • 179 Accesses

Abstract

In this introduction, we explain how the chapters in this volume give support to the idea that different accounts of active cognition in the history of philosophy directly or indirectly respond to Aristotle’s account of cognition in his De anima.

This volume was produced with the financial support of Riksbanken Jubileumsfond, Sweden. A first version of some of the articles gathered here was prepared for the workshop “Activity and Passivity in Cognition”, organised in the framework of the research programme “Representation and Reality. Historical and Contemporary Perspectives on the Aristotelian Tradition” (funded by Riksbanken Jubileumsfond) at the University of Gothenburg (Sweden). Their common goal was to discuss the different ways in which Aristotle’s account of cognition, according to which thinking is some sort of affection, was variously discussed and criticised in the history of Western philosophy. We would like to thank Colin Guthrie King for his valuable help with the last version of this introduction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For Aristotle’s account of sensation, see Sorabji (1992), Everson (1997), Burnyeat (2002). See also Sorabji’s critique of Burnyeat’s position, in Sorabji (2001).

  2. 2.

    Cf. Aristotle, De anima III.4.429a13–15.

  3. 3.

    Cf. Aristotle, De anima III.5.430a10–14. The literature on this passage is extensive; see especially Kosman (1992), Frede (1996), Caston (1999).

  4. 4.

    See Moraux (1978) and Magrin (2011).

  5. 5.

    See Davidson (1992).

  6. 6.

    See Barbotin (1954), Ierodiakonou (2016), De Haas in this volume.

  7. 7.

    See Ierodiakonou (2016).

  8. 8.

    Cf. Aristotle, GA 736b27.

  9. 9.

    Alexander, DA, 98.9–10.

  10. 10.

    See Moraux (1942) and Tuominen (2006, 2010).

  11. 11.

    See Blumenthal (1987) and Balldriaux (1989).

  12. 12.

    See Davidson (1992).

  13. 13.

    On the controversy about the relation between Alexander and Plotinus, see Schroeder (1984).

  14. 14.

    See Blumenthal (1971), Emilsson (2007, 148), Chiaradonna (2012).

  15. 15.

    See Gerson (2018).

  16. 16.

    See Hutchinson (2018, 143).

  17. 17.

    Augustine, Confessionum, VII, 8, VII, 20.

  18. 18.

    Cf. Augustine, De quantitate animae, XXIII, 41: “[…] quod patitur sensus non laetere animam […]”; see O’Daly (1987).

  19. 19.

    See, e.g., Wassmer (1960); cf. Augustine, De civitate dei, X, 2, 1.

  20. 20.

    Cf. Augustine, De trinitate, X, X, 19.

  21. 21.

    For Olivi’s theory of cognition, see Toivanen (2013).

  22. 22.

    Peter John Olivi, In Sent., II, q.58, 413: “Sed intelligere et velle, secundum hoc quod active sumuntur, potius denominant mentem nostram et potentias nostras quam obiecta sua vel quam aliqua alia agentia, nos enim dicimur volentes et intelligentes, obiecta vero solum dicuntur intellecta et volita”.

  23. 23.

    Peter John Olivi, In Sent., II, q.72, 9: “[…] quantumcumque potentia cognitiva per habitum et species ab actione cognitiva differente sit informata, non potest in actionem cognitivam exire, nisi prius intendat actualiter in obiectum, ita quod aspectus suae intentionis sit actualiter conversus et directus in illud.”

  24. 24.

    Peter John Olivi, In Sent., II, q.58, 419: “[…] non omne quod necessario praeexigitur ad productionem alicuius est causa effectiva ipsius […]. Et sic dico quod obiecta voluntatis liberae […] non praeexiguntur ad eius actus liberos ad aliquid efficiendum seu coefficiendum in ipsis actibus, sed solum ad terminandum aspectum potentiae agentis […]”.

  25. 25.

    Cf. Perler (2003, 65); see also Pasnau (1997) and Toivanen (2013).

  26. 26.

    Peter John Olivi, In Sent., II, q.58, 477–478: “[…] potentiae habent per se sufficientem virtutem activam suorum actuum absque aliqua cooperatione seu coefficientia facta ab obiectis seu speciebus […] quia fere omnes rationes quibus probatur aut probari potest potentiam intellectivam et alias potentias inferiores non esse sufficienter activas respectu actuum suorum possunt aeque bene adduci ad probandum hoc ipsum […] de voluntate, in quantum est libera […]. Approbare autem sic huiusmodi rationes est idem quod dicere illas rationes esse veras et necessarias quibus concluditur voluntatem nullo modo esse liberam […]. Quod est destruere […] omnem fidem et legem et gratiam et culpam et omne bonum.”

  27. 27.

    See Decaix (Forthcoming).

  28. 28.

    Brentano (1867).

  29. 29.

    See Mora-M´arquez (2019).

  30. 30.

    See, e.g., Pasnau (1997), Bakker and Thijsen (2007), Lagerlund (2010), Silva and Yrjönsuuri (2014).

References

  • Alexander of Aphrodisias. (2008). De anima. In R. W. Sharples (Ed.), Alexander Aphrodisiensis De anima libri mantissa: A new edition of the Greek text with introduction and commentary. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. (1939). De quantitate animae. In P. de Labriolle (Ed.), Dialogues philosophiques II (Biblioth`eque Augustinienne, Vol. 5, pp. 226–396). Paris: Descl´ee de Brouwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. (1955). De civitate dei. In B. Dombard & A. Kalb. Corpus (Eds.), De civitate dei. Libri I–X (Christianorum Series Latina, Vol. 47). Turnhout: Brepols.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. (1968). De trinitate. In W. J. Mountain (Ed.), De Trinitate libri XV (Corpus christianorum Series Latina, Vol. 50–50A). Turnhout: Brepols.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. (1972). De Gen. ad litt. In P. Agaësse & A. Solignac (Eds.), De Genesi ad litteram libri duodecim, VIII–XII (Biblioth`eque Augustinienne, Vol. 49). Paris: Descl´ee de Brouwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine. (1981). Confessionum. In L. Verheijen (Ed.), Sancti Augustini Confessionum libri XIII (Corpus christianorum Series Latina, Vol. 27). Turnhout: Brepols.

    Google Scholar 

  • Averroes. (1953). In De an. In F. S. Crawford (Ed.), Averrois Cordubensis commentarium magnum in Aristotelis De anima libros (Corpus commentariorum Averrois in Aristotelem VI, Vol. 1). Cambridge, MA: The Academy of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakker, P. J. J. M., & Thijsen, J. M. M. H. (Eds.). (2007). Mind, cognition and representation. The tradition of commentaries on Aristotle’s De anima. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balldriaux, O. (1989). Themistius et l’ex´eg`ese de la no´etique aristot´elicienne. Revue de philosophie ancienne, 7, 199–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbotin, Edmond. (1954). La thˊeorie aristotˊelicienne de l’intellect d’aprˋes Thˊeophraste. Louvain: Publications Universitaires de Louvain.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal, H. J. (1971). Plotinus’ psychology. His doctrines of the embodied soul. La Hague: M. Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blumenthal, H. J. (1987). Alexander of Aphrodisias in the later Greek commentaries on Aristotle’s De anima. In J. Wiesner (Ed.), Aristoteles: Werk und Wirkung (Vol. II, pp. 90–106). Berlin-New York: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1867). Die Psychologie des Aristoteles, insbesondere seine Lehre vom NOUS POIETICOS. Mainz: Franz Kirchheim.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. F. (2002). De anima II.5. Phronesis 47(1), 28–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (1999). Aristotle’s two intellects: A modest proposal. Phronesis, 44(3), 199–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiaradonna, R. (2012). Plotinus’ account of the cognitive powers of the soul: Sense perception and discursive thought. Topoi, 31(2), 191–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, H. A. (1992). Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on intellect. Their cosmologies, theories of the active intellect and theories of human intellect. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Decaix, V. (Forthcoming). L’aiguillion de l’affect. Le sens de la conscience chez Pierre de Jean Olivi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duns Scotus. (1963). Ordinatio I, dist. 26–48. In Opera Omnia (Vol. 6). Vatican: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emilsson, E. K. (2007). Plotinus on intellect. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Everson, S. (1997). Aristotle on perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flasch, K. (1972). Kennt die mittelalterische Philosophie die konstitutive Funktion des menschlichen Denkens? Eine Untersuchung zu Dietrich von Freiberg. Kant Studies, 63, 182–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Francisco Su´arez. (1856–1861). Disputationes metaphysicae. In: Opera Omnia (Vol. 26–27). Paris: Viv`es.

    Google Scholar 

  • Francisco Su´arez. (1978–1991). In De anima. In S. Castellote Cubells (Ed.), Commentaria una cum quaestionibus in libros Aristotelis de anima (3 Vols.). Madrid: Labor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frede, M. (1996). La th´eorie aristot´elicienne de l’intellect agent. In G. Romeyer-Dherbey & C. Viano (Eds.), Corps et âme: Sur le De anima d’Aristote (pp. 377–390). Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerson, L. P. (2018). Plotinus. In A. Marmodoro & S. Cartwright (Eds.), A history of mind and body in late antiquity (pp. 67–84). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchinson, D. M. (2018). Plotinus on Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ierodiakonou, K. (2016). Theophrastus. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/theophrastus/

  • Kosman, A. (1992). What does the maker mind make? In M. Nussbaum & A. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima (pp. 343–358). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagerlund, H. (2010). Forming the mind. Essays on the internal senses and the mind/body problem from Avicenna to the medical enlightenment. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magrin, S. (2011). Theophrastus, Alexander, and Themistius on Aristotle’s De anima III.4–5. In R. Wisnovsky et al. (Eds.), Vehicles of transmission, translation, and transformation in medieval textual culture (pp. 49–74). Turnhout: Brepols.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mora-M´arquez, A. M. (2019). Singular intellection in medieval commentaries on Aristotle’s De anima. Vivarium, 57(3–4), 293–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moraux, P. (1942). Alexandre d’Aphrodise. Exˊegˋete de la Noˊetique d’Aristote. Paris: E. Droz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moraux, P. (1978). Le De anima dans la tradition grecque: quelques aspects de l’interpr´etation du trait´e, de Th´eophraste `a Th´emistius. In G. E. R. Lloyd & G. E. L. Owen (Eds.), Aristotle on mind and the senses. Proceedings of the Seventh Symposium Aristotelicum (pp. 280–324). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Daly, G. (1987). Augustine’s philosophy of mind. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau. R. (1997). Theories of cognition in the later middle ages. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perler, D. (Ed.). (2003). Thˊeories de l’intentionnalitˊe au Moyen Âge. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peter John Olivi. (1926). In Sent. II. In B. Jansen (Ed.), Quaestiones in secundum librum Sententiarum (Vol. 3). Quaracchi: S. Bonaventurae.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, F. M. (1984). Light and the active intellect in Alexander and Plotinus. Hermes, 112(2), 239–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silva, J. F., & Yrjönsuuri, M. (Eds.). (2014). Active perception in the history of philosophy: From Plato to modern philosophy. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (1992). Intentionality and physiological processes: Aristotle’s theory of sense-perception. In M. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle’s De anima (pp. 195–225). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (2001). Aristotle on sensory processes and intentionality. A reply to Myles Burnyeat. In D. Perler (Ed.), Ancient and Medieval Theories of Intentionality (pp. 49–63). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (1930). Contra gentiles. In Summa contra gentiles III. Opera omnia t. XIII. Roma: Commissio Leonina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (1933). In sent. In M. F. Moos (Ed.), Scriptum super sententiis magistri Petri Lombardi, d. 1–21, t. III. Paris: Lethielleux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (1950). In De anima. In Sentencia libri de anima. Opera omnia t. XLV/1. Rome: Commissio Leonina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (1970). De veritate. In Quaestiones disputatae de veritate. Quaestiones 1–7. Opera omnia t. XXII/1.2. Rome: Commissio Leonina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (1972). De veritate. In Quaestiones disputatae de veritate. Quaestiones 8–20. Opera omnia t. XXII/2.1. Rome: Commissio Leonina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (1973). De veritate. In Quaestiones disputatae de veritate. Quaestiones 21–29. Opera omnia t. XXII/3.1. Rome: Commission Leonina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (1988). ST Ia. In Prima pars summae theologiae. Opera omnia t. IV. Rome: Commissio Leonina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (1996). Quaestiones disputatae de anima. In: Opera omnia, t. XXIV/1. Rome-Paris: Commissio Leonina, Cerf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas Aquinas. (Forthcoming). De potentia. In: Quaestiones de potentia Dei. Opera Omnia t. XXI. Rome: Comission Leonina.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toivanen, J. (2013). Perception and the internal senses. Peter John Olivi on the cognitive functions of the sensitive soul. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuominen, M. (2006). Aristotle and Alexander of Aphrodisias on the active intellect. In V. Hirvonen, T. J. Holopainen, & M. Tuominen Mind and modality: Studies in the history of philosophy in Honour of Simo Knuuttila (pp. 55–70). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuominen, M. (2010). Receptive reason: Alexander of Aphrodisias on material intellect. Phronesis, 55, 170–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wassmer, T. A. (1960). The trinitarian theology of augustine and his debt to Plotinus. Harvard Theological Review, 53(4), 261–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ana María Mora-Márquez .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Decaix, V., Mora-Márquez, A.M. (2020). Introduction. In: Decaix, V., Mora-Márquez, A. (eds) Active Cognition. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-35304-9_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics