Skip to main content

Tocqueville’s Philosophy of History: Its Meaning and Implications for Russia and Central and Eastern Europe

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Exploring the Social and Political Economy of Alexis de Tocqueville

Part of the book series: Mercatus Studies in Political and Social Economy ((MSPSE))

Abstract

For philosophers of history, historical analyses are worthwhile not solely for what they reveal about the past, but for the light they shed on the present and their implications for the future. In their attempts to discern laws that governed prior epochs, philosophers of history raise many questions. Not typically regarded as a philosopher of history, per se, Alexis de Tocqueville poses many of the same questions asked by thinkers who are; exploring and synthesizing Tocqueville’s answers is one aim of this chapter. A second goal of the chapter is to assess the meaning and relevance of Tocqueville’s philosophy of history for Russia, in particular, and post-communist Central and Eastern Europe, more generally.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Harvey Mitchell notes that Tocqueville resisted calling himself a philosopher and had a “professed disdain for philosophy.” But, Mitchell avers, while “it is impossible to ignore… it is also possible to exaggerate” these “declarations of alienation from philosophy” (1996: 8).

  2. 2.

    Sheldon Wolin writes that “it is difficult to claim… that Tocqueville employed a clear conception of class analysis; his main concern was with classes as political actors” (2009: 635 n 35). And other authors note that in his accounting of revolutions, Tocqueville offers an analysis strongly at odds with Karl Marx’s (which is more clearly and obviously focused on class).

  3. 3.

    Tocqueville’s pairing of the term “philosophic” with the description of men with few desires or needs is curious. It stands in contrast with Rousseau’s description of natural man, who has few needs: “it is not possible to conceive why someone who had neither desires nor fears would take the trouble to reason” (1997: 142).

  4. 4.

    Tocqueville’s emphasis.

  5. 5.

    Of revolutions, for instance, he insists: “every revolution leaves its mark and raises the level. God wills it! His work must be allowed to proceed” (Tocqueville 2016: 229).

  6. 6.

    For an example of social science research that explains and makes use of these concepts, see, for instance James Mahoney, J. (2001) Path-Dependent Explanations of Regime Change: Central America in Comparative Perspective. Studies in Comparative International Development 36 (1): 111–141.

  7. 7.

    Another critical juncture Tocqueville identifies is when French monarchs divided classes from one another, which he says led to almost all other problems for the monarchy (2008: 138). Elsewhere, Tocqueville writes that if there had been a Frederick II for France, monarchy would not have strengthened itself the way it did (2008: 164). Speaking of the Revolution of 1848, he notes that “half an hour” could have altered the destiny of France, but that once certain actions had been taken, the stage was set (2016: 42).

  8. 8.

    “The theory of continuous and indefinite improvement of man took root” (Tocqueville 2008: 175).

  9. 9.

    Mass democracy is certainly a new phenomenon. But, as James Kloppenberg notes, Tocqueville looked to the advent of democracy “always with a mixture of optimism and pessimism” (2006: 520).

  10. 10.

    Stefan Hedlund (2005) employs the logic of path dependency to survey Russia’s historical development. His analysis extends to periods well-before Peter I ascended to the throne.

  11. 11.

    Tsar Nicholas II introduced the Duma in 1906 as a concession to revolutionary demands made a year prior. Like the 1917 Revolution, the 1905 revolution emerged after a period of reform. Specifically, the earlier revolution followed the emancipation of the serfs in 1861, which increased the freedoms enjoyed by the peasants, without significantly decreasing the hardships they faced. For more on the Revolutions of 1905 and 1917, see Pipes, R. (1995) A Concise History of the Russian Revolution. New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.

  12. 12.

    Adversaries who refused to follow Gorbachev’s lead and resisted reform also fell from power, as revolutions spread from one part of the communist sphere to another, reinforcing and playing off one another.

  13. 13.

    We may draw from recent social science research to support Tocqueville’s claims that both historical legacies and agency bear on the structure and functioning of societies. Marc Morjé Howard (2002) convincingly argues that the weakness of civil society across post-communist Central and Eastern Europe is attributable to the communist experience. But, as Timothy Frye (1997) notes, the communist legacy cannot explain every facet of post-communist society. While there may be a temptation to attribute the strong presidencies that exist in, for example, Russia and Belarus to the shared communist experience, this explanation founders when we consider that a strong presidency is not a feature that all or most post-communist countries share; a country’s having a strong or weak presidency is a result of decisions made by political actors in that country. Peter Leeson and William Trumbull compare Russia with other former Soviet states and with the post-communist world more broadly to show that “Russia could have done much better” at transitioning to democracy and capitalism. Though it started out with a similar set of circumstances as other transitioning countries, Russia is decisively in the middle or worse when compared with these countries in terms of various economic indicators, perceived levels of corruption, press freedom, and political freedom (2006: 247).

  14. 14.

    A will for liberty can develop over the course of a generation. In “about 1750,” Frenchmen were not “demanding in the matter of political liberty,” interested in “reforms more than rights.” By 1770, “the position was no longer the same; the image of political liberty had imprinted itself on Frenchmen’s minds” (Tocqueville 2008: 164–5).

  15. 15.

    What Tocqueville says about peoples, James Buchanan echoes when discussing persons, that is, individuals: “the thirst and desire for freedom, and responsibility, is perhaps not nearly so universal as so many post-Enlightenment philosophers have assumed.” “Many persons are, indeed, afraid to be free” (Buchanan 2005: 23–24).

  16. 16.

    For more on Tocqueville and Russia or Central and Eastern Europe, see Craiutu (2014); Rutland, P. Democracy in Russia: A Tocquevillean Perspective. In: A. Craiutu and S. Gellar (eds) Conversations with Tocqueville: The Global Democratic Revolution the Twenty-First Century. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 199–223; Thurston, G. J. (1976) Alexis De Tocqueville in Russia. Journal of the History of Ideas, 37 (2): 289–306.

References

  • Acton, E. (1995) Russia: the Tsarist and Soviet Legacy. New York, NY: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan J. M. (2005) Afraid To Be Free: Dependency as Desideratum. In: W. F. Shughart and R. D Tollison (eds) Policy Challenges and Political Responses. Springer, Boston, MA, pp. 19–31.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chaadayev, P. (1976) Philosophical Letters. In: J. Edie, J. Scanlan, and M-B Zeldin (eds) The Beginnings of Russian Philosophy: The Slavophiles; The Westernizers, vol. 1 of Russian Philosophy. Knoxville, TN: University of Tennessee Press, pp. 106–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condorcet, Marquis de (1969) Outline of an Historical Picture of the Progress of the Human Mind (excerpts). In W. W. Wagar (ed.) The Idea of Progress Since the Renaissance. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., pp. 75–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craiutu, A. (2014) Tocqueville and Eastern Europe. In: Christine Dunn Henderson (ed.) Tocqueville’s Voyages: The Evolution of His Ideas and Their Journey beyond His Time. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, pp. 390–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frye, T. (1997) A Politics of Institutional Choice: Post-Communist Presidencies. Comparative Political Studies, 3(5): 523–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedlund, S. (2005) Russian Path Dependence: a People with a Troubled History. London, UK: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, M. (2002) The Weakness of Postcommunist Civil Society. Journal of Democracy 13(1): 157–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, A. S. (2010) Alexis de Tocqueville. New York, NY: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kloppenberg, J. T. (2006) The Canvas And The Color: Tocqueville’s “Philosophical History” And Why It Matters Now. Modern Intellectual History 3(3): 495–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. T. and Trumbull, W. N. (2006) Comparing Apples: Normalcy, Russia, and the Remaining Post-Socialist World. Post-Soviet Affairs 22(3): 225–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machiavelli, N. (2016) The Prince. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahoney, J. (2001) Path-Dependent Explanations of Regime Change: Central America in Comparative Perspective. Studies in Comparative International Development 36(1): 111–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, H. (1996) Individual Choice and the Structures of History: Alexis De Tocqueville as Historian Reappraised. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pipes, R. (1995) A Concise History of the Russian Revolution. New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (1997) “The Discourses” and Other Early Political Writings. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutland, P. (2009) Democracy in Russia: A Tocquevillean Perspective. In A. Craiutu and S. Gellar (eds) Conversations with Tocqueville: The Global Democratic Revolution the Twenty-First Century. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, pp. 199–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thurston, G. J. (1976) Alexis De Tocqueville in Russia. Journal of the History of Ideas 37(2): 289–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tocqueville, A. (2008) The Ancien Régime and the French Revolution. New York, NY: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tocqueville, A. (2003) Democracy in America: and Two Essays on America. New York, NY: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tocqueville, A. (1996) Fortnight in the Wilderness. In: G. W. Pierson (ed) Tocqueville in America. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 229–289.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tocqueville, A (2016) Recollections: the French Revolution of 1848 and Its Aftermath. Charlottesville, VA: University of Virginia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolin, S. S. (2009) Tocqueville between Two Worlds: The Making of a Political and Theoretical Life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Slaboch, M. (2020). Tocqueville’s Philosophy of History: Its Meaning and Implications for Russia and Central and Eastern Europe. In: Boettke, P., Martin, A. (eds) Exploring the Social and Political Economy of Alexis de Tocqueville. Mercatus Studies in Political and Social Economy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34937-0_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34937-0_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-34936-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-34937-0

  • eBook Packages: Economics and FinanceEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics