Skip to main content

The Relativity of Reality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Viewpoint Relativism

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 419))

  • 345 Accesses

Abstract

According to conceptual relativism, reality crucially depends on the mind and the language of a person. The world does not present itself as already made or arranged. People have different ways of categorising and conceptualising the world. Because according to conceptual relativism, what exists also depends on conceptual frameworks, it can also be called ontological relativism. We must note that ontological relativism does not mean that the mind creates or generates reality and its objects as a craftsman creates a ceramic object. That would be idealism. Relativism does not deny that the world exists and affects our senses, experiences and knowledge. But despite this, we cannot know how the world is in itself. We do not have an absolute point of view that would reveal reality to us as it is. We must always build our world from some chosen conceptual foundation. In this chapter, I will first define what conceptual relativism is. Then, I will discuss natural kinds and the problematics of structuring reality. I will then present and compare Putnam’s internal realism and Searle’s external realism. In the last section, I will present how we can analyse and specify the central questions of conceptual relativism about individuation and categorisation using the theory of conceptual spaces.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Baghramian (2004); O’Grady (2002).

  2. 2.

    See Hautamäki (1983b, 1983c, 1985).

  3. 3.

    Niiniluoto also calls his approach conceptual pluralism; see Niiniluoto (1987, 1999, 2014). I will return to this in the following chapter.

  4. 4.

    About natural kinds see Giere (2006), van Fraassen (2008), Tahko (2015), Toledo (2015).

  5. 5.

    Social constructionism is a general theory about the construction of reality, but here I will only focus on its use in social and cultural research (cf. Fuller, 2006; Hacking , 1999; Pulkkinen, 1996).

  6. 6.

    My impression is that social constructionism is mainly devoted to societies and cultures, not to nature.

  7. 7.

    Hacking denies that Searle represents social constructionism. I consider Searle’s book The Construction of Social Reality to be the analysis of in what sense society is constructed, and in what sense it is not.

  8. 8.

    It should be noted that although the fields of the philosophy of science and science studies have discussed the concept of social constructionism a lot (see Giere , 2006; Fuller, 2006), it is not widely used in epistemological discussions on relativism. For example, in her encompassing work, Relativism (2004), Baghramian does not mention social constructionism or refer to Berger and Luckmann’s classical work, The Social Construction of Reality (1967). O’Grady (2002) and Mosteller (2008) also do not refer to social constructionism.

  9. 9.

    Putnam reiterates this critique in his last work; see Putnam (2015).

  10. 10.

    Putnam avoids using the term “conceptual relativism” in the context of his own theory.

  11. 11.

    Jaakko Hintikka offers an interesting differentiation between two kinds of identifications. A perspectival identification takes place from the perspective and context of the speaker. A public identification is perspective-free. In Hintikka’s semantics, these include the different identifications of the entities between possible worlds. See Hintikka (1998). I would like to thank Niiniluoto for this observation.

  12. 12.

    Niiniluoto (1999, 2014) adopted a similar account of truth in relation to different frameworks. I criticise it in Chap. 7.

  13. 13.

    The relationship between framework-reality has been described using the concepts of Kantian scheme and content, with the thought that the scheme provides a shape and structure to a material that is considered to be the content (Baghramian , 2004, pp. 214–218).

  14. 14.

    However, because Putnam rejected the epistemic concept of truth in his later work and started supporting a “metaphysical” concept of truth (truth is not warranted assertability under ideal conditions, Putnam, 2015), even the last differences between internal realism and Searle’s external realism disappears.

  15. 15.

    Charro and Colomina (2013) assume that “the physical world has a determinate/determinable structure,” cf. also the metaphysical theory of points of view in Colomina-Almiñana (2018).

  16. 16.

    Gärdenfors (2000, p. 24) treats colour as a three-dimensional continuous domain, where the dimensions of hue, chromaticness, and brightness are integral in the sense that one cannot assign an object a value in one dimension without giving it a value in the other. In my presentation, I suppose that all domains are separate, like colour and shape are separate, and integral dimensions are integrated into one multi-dimensional domain.

  17. 17.

    “Natural” does not mean naturalistic, but non-artificial.

  18. 18.

    Decock and Douven (2015) defined relative identity by applying the metrics of domains. In their definition, identity means high-similarity in all relevant domains.

  19. 19.

    This kind of ontology resembles the so-called cluster theory of individuals, according to which objects are a cluster or bundle of properties.

  20. 20.

    In Kaipainen and Hautamäki (2011, 2015), the concept of representation space is introduced; it is a lower-dimensional space, where categorisation of ontospace is represented and studied. Representation space is dependent on perspectives.

  21. 21.

    Personally, I do not see that convexity should be a part of criterion C. There are so many useful concepts without convexity, especially in science, that the convexity requirement restricts the scope of applications of conceptual space theory too much.

  22. 22.

    This refers to the semantic or structuralist concept of theories. I will say more about it in the next chapter.

References

  • Baghramian, M. (2004). Relativism. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, P., & Luckmann, T. (1967). The social construction of reality. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1980). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. In H. Morick (Ed.), Challenges to empiricism (pp. 46–70). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charro, F., & Colomina, J. J. (2013). Points of view beyond models, towards a formal approach to points of view as access to the world. Foundations of Science, 19(2), 137–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colomina-Almiñana, J. J. (2018). Formal approach to the metaphysics of perspectives: Points of view as access. Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Decock, L., & Douven, I. (2015). Conceptual spaces as philosophers’ tool. In F. Zenker & P. Gärdenfors (Eds.), Applications of conceptual space (Synthese Library, 359) (pp. 207–221). Heidelberg, Germany/New York/Dordrecht, The Netherlands/London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1920). Reconstruction in philosophy. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1929). The quest for security. A study of the relation of knowledge and action. London: George Allen and Unwin LTD..

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., & Gärdenfors, P. (Forthcoming). What are natural concepts? A design perspective. Mind and Language.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Taylor, C. (2015). Retrieving realism. Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. (2006). The philosophy of science and technology studies. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H. -G. (1992). Truth and method (2nd ed., Trans. Weinsheimer, J., & Marshall, D. G.). New York: Crossroad.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual spaces: On the geometry of thought. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1973). Ontological relativity and relative identity. In M. K. Munitz (Ed.), Logic and ontology (pp. 287–302). New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1978). The ways of worldmaking. Sussex, UK: The Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harding, S. (2015). Objectivity & diversity, another logic of scientific research. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hautamäki, A. (1983b). The logic of viewpoints. Studia Logica, 42(2/3), 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hautamäki, A. (1983c). Dialectics and points of view. Ajatus, 39, 218–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hautamäki, A. (1985). Epistemologinen relativismi. [Epistemological Relativism]. Ajatus, 42, 22–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hautamäki, A. (1986). Points of view and their logical analysis (Acta Philosophica Fennica, 41). Helsinki, Finland: Societas Philosophica Fennica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hautamäki, A. (1992). A conceptual space approach to semantic networks. Computers & Mathematics with Applications, 23(6–9), 517–525. Reprinted in F. Lehmann (Ed.), Semantic networks in artificial intelligence (pp. 517–525). Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hautamäki, A. (2015). Change, event, and temporal points of view. In M. Vázquez & M. Liz (Eds.), Temporal points of view, subjective and objective aspects (pp. 197–221). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hautamäki, A. (2016). Points of view, a conceptual space approach. Foundations of Science, 21, 493–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1972). Semantics for propositional attitudes. In A. Marras (Ed.), Intentionality, mind and language (pp. 457–472). Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1998). Perspectival identification, demonstratives and “small worlds”. Synthese, 114, 203–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, W. E. (1964). Logic. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaipainen, M., & Hautamäki, A. (2011). Epistemic pluralism and multi-perspective knowledge organization, explorative conceptualization of topical content domains. Knowledge Organization, 38(6), 503–514.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaipainen, M., & Hautamäki, A. (2015). A perspectivist approach to conceptual spaces. In F. Zenker & P. Gärdenfors (Eds.), Applications of conceptual spaces, the case for geometric knowledge representation (Synthese library, 359) (pp. 245–258). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaipainen, M., & Hautamäki, A. (2019). Seeking for the grasp: An iterative subdivision model of conceptualisation. In M. Kaipainen, F. Zenker, A. Hautamäki, & P. Gärdenfors (Eds.), Conceptual spaces: Elaborations and applications (Synthese Library, 405) (pp. 103–123). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1956). Mind and the world order, outline of a theory of knowledge. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mosteller, T. (2008). Relativism. A guide for the perplexed. London/New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Critical scientific realism. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2014). Against relative truth. In K. Mulligan, K. Kijania-Placek, & T. Placek (Eds.), The history and philosophy of Polish logic: Essays in honour of Jan Woleński (pp. 141–159). Basingstoke, UK: The Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Grady, P. (2002). Relativism. Chesham, UK: Aucumen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pulkkinen, T. (1996). The postmodern and political agency. Helsinki, Finland: Department of Philosophy, University of Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1978). Realism and reason. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Meaning and the moral sciences (pp. 123–138). Boston/London/Henly: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth and history. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1988). Representation and reality. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2004). Ethics without ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2015). Naturalism, realism, and normativity. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(02), 312–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1972). The world well lost. The Journal of Philosophy, 69(10), 649–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (2007). Freedom and neurobiology, reflections on free will, language, and political power. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tahko, T. E. (2015). Natural kind essentialism revisited. Mind, 124(495), 795–822.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toledo, S. A. (2015). Kinds, laws and perspectives. In M. Vázquez & M. Liz (Eds.), Temporal points of view, subjective and objective aspects (pp. 235–253). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958c). On certainty (Uber Gewissheit) (Ed. Anscombe, G. E. M., & von Wright, G. H., Trans. Paul, D., & Anscombe, G. E. M.). Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zenker, F., & Gärdenfors, P. (Eds.). (2015). Applications of conceptual spaces. The case for geometric knowledge representation. Synthese library (Vol. 359). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hautamäki, A. (2020). The Relativity of Reality. In: Viewpoint Relativism. Synthese Library, vol 419. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34595-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics