Skip to main content

Preference for Flexibility: A Continuous Representation in an Ordinal Setup

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 316 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in Systems, Decision and Control ((SSDC,volume 263))

Abstract

In a menu-choice framework with a compact metric space of alternatives, I prove a representation of preference for flexibility that features continuous ex-post utility functions as well as a continuous aggregator over ex-post utility levels. Continuity of the ex-post utility functions ensures that each function attains its maximum on any compact menu of alternatives. This, in turn, supports the standard interpretation that relates the value of flexibility to the maximization of ex-post preferences. I also show that an incomplete menu-preference is characterized by the Pareto order induced by a collection of aggregators, in place of a single one.

I wrote the first draft of this paper in 2007, when I was a Ph.D. student at New York University, which circulated under the title “An Ordinal, Continuous Representation Theorem for Preference for Flexibility.” I owe special thanks to Efe Ok, who was my advisor at the time. I also thank Barton Lipman, Pietro Ortoleva, Clemens Puppe, Debraj Ray, Gil Riella, two anonymous referees and the editors of this volume for useful discussions and suggestions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    To mention a few examples, the proof of Gul and Pesendorfer’s [20] representation appeals to the von Neumann–Morgenstern representation theorem, whereas Dekel, Lipman and Rustichini [8] build upon some classical results in functional analysis such as the Hahn-Banach extension theorem and the Riesz representation theorem.

  2. 2.

    For instance, the independence axiom of Dekel, Lipman and Rustichini [8] combined with the monotonicity axiom implies Kreps’ [24] submodularity property [8, Footnote 21]. While the independence axiom becomes irrelevant in an ordinal setup, submodularity is still indispensable, which arguably makes the latter more substantive as regards the notion of preference for flexibility.

  3. 3.

    Representations of this sort arise in the analysis of preference for flexibility and related notions such as liquidity demand for money (see, e.g., [17, 18]). Multi-preference approach to the measurement of value of freedom of choice is another related area of research (see, e.g., [2]). Bleichrodt and Quiggin [3] provide a more recent application to health economics.

  4. 4.

    “ If ...\(\dot{\succsim }\) is represented ...with \(U(\cdot ,s)\) continuous for each s..., then \(\dot{\succsim }\) is continuous on \(X^{c}\). The converse seems reasonable: If \(\dot{\succsim }\) is continuous on \(X^{c}\), then a representation with continuous \(U(\cdot ,s)\) and u is possible. But I am unable to supply a proof of the converse—U as constructed in the proof of the theorem will be lower semi-continuous only” (Kreps [24, p. 575]). Here, \(X^{c}\) stands for the collection of menus, \(\dot{\succsim }\) is the DM’s preference relation over menus, u denotes the aggregator, and \(U(\cdot ,s)\) is a state-dependent utility function.

  5. 5.

    Recent reviews of this literature can be found in [4, 5] for representations with single and multiple utility functions, respectively.

  6. 6.

    In Kochov’s model, a prior refers to a probability distribution over subjective states, or state-dependent utility functions. Each prior defines an expectation operator over ex-post utility levels, which corresponds to an additive aggregator in the present setup (see Footnote 8).

  7. 7.

    The Hausdorff distance between \(A,B\in \mathcal {K} (\mathcal {X})\) equals the maximum of \(\max _{a\in A}\min _{b\in B}\sigma (a,b)\) and \(\max _{b\in B}\min _{a\in A}\sigma (a,b),\) where \(\sigma \) stands for the metric on \(\mathcal {X}\).

  8. 8.

    For a finite set of utility functions U, a (monotonic) additive aggregator \(\varphi \) is defined by nonnegative numbers \(\alpha _{u} (u\in U)\) such that \(\varphi \left( \max _{A}U\right) =\sum _{u\in U}\alpha _{u}\max _{a\in A}u(a)\) for every \(A\in \mathcal {K} (\mathcal {A})\). When U is infinite, the summation operator is replaced by the expectation operator induced by a probability measure on U.

  9. 9.

    More generally, Gorno [19] shows that any complete and transitive preference relation on nonempty subsets of a finite set can be represented with an additive aggregator over state-dependent utility levels. The distinctive feature of Kreps’ version is that each state-dependent utility function has a nonnegative weight, in line with the monotonicity axiom (see Footnote 8).

  10. 10.

    Specifically, for every \(\varphi \in \Phi \), we can find a finite capacity \(\eta _{\varphi }\) on the set U such that for every \(A\in \mathcal {K}(\mathcal {A}),\) \(\varphi \left( \max _{A}U\right) =\int _{0}^{\infty }\eta _{\varphi }\left( \left\{ u\in U:\max _{a\in A}u(a)\ge \alpha \right\} \right) d\alpha .\) (A finite capacity \(\eta \) on U is a real valued function on the collection of all subsets of U such that \(\eta (\emptyset )=0,\) \(\eta (U)<\infty \), and \(\eta (V)\le \eta (W)\) whenever \(V\subseteq W\subseteq U.\))

References

  1. Arlegi, R., Nieto, J.: Incomplete preferences and the preference for flexibility. Math. Soc. Sci. 41, 151–165 (2001)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. Arrow, K.J.: A note on freedom and flexibility. In: Basu, K., Pattanaik, P., Suzumura, K. (eds.) Choice, Welfare, and Development. A Festschrift in Honour of Amartya K. Sen, pp. 7–16. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bleichrodt, H., Quiggin, J.: Capabilities as menus: a non-welfarist basis for QALY evaluation. J. Health Econ. 32, 128–137 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Bosi, G., Caterino, A., Ceppitelli, R.: Existence of continuous utility functions for arbitrary binary relations: some sufficient conditions. Tatra Mt. Math. Publ. 46, 15–27 (2010)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Bosi, G., Herden, G.: On continuous multi-utility representations of semi-closed and closed preorders. Math. Soc. Sci. 79, 20–29 (2016)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  6. Danan, E.: A Behavioral Model of Individual Welfare. Université de Paris, Mimeo (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Danan, E., Ziegelmeyer, A.: Are preferences complete? An experimental measurement of indecisiveness under risk. Max Planck Institute of Economics, Mimeo (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Dekel, E., Lipman, B.L., Rustichini, A.: Representing preferences with a unique subjective state space. Econometrica 69, 891–934 (2001)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  9. Dekel, E., Lipman, B.L., Rustichini, A.: Temptation-driven preferences. Rev. Econ. Stud. 76, 937–971 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  10. Dillenberger, D., Sadowski, P.: Ashamed to be selfish. Theor. Econ. 7, 99–124 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  11. Dubra, J., Maccheroni, F., Ok, E.A.: Expected utility theory without the completeness axiom. J. Econ. Theory 115, 118–133 (2004)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Ergin, H.: Costly Contemplation. Mimeo, MIT (2003)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Ergin, H., Sarver, T.: A unique costly contemplation representation. Econometrica 78, 1285–1339 (2010)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. Evren, Ö., Minardi, S.: Warm-glow giving and freedom to be selfish. Econ. J. 127, 1381–1409 (2017)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Evren, Ö., Ok, E.A.: On the multi-utility representation of preference relations. J. Math. Econ. 47, 554–563 (2011)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  16. Foster, J.E.: Freedom, opportunity, and well-being. In: Arrow, K.J., Sen, A.K., Suzumura, K. (eds.) Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, vol. 2, pp. 687–728. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2011)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. Goldman, S.M.: Flexibility and the demand for money. J. Econ. Theory 9, 203–222 (1974)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Goldman, S.M.: Portfolio choice and flexibility: the precautionary motive. J. Monet. Econ. 4, 263–280 (1978)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Gorno, L.: Additive representation for preferences over menus in finite choice settings. J. Math. Econ. 65, 41–47 (2016)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  20. Gul, F., Pesendorfer, W.: Temptation and self-control. Econometrica 69, 1403–1435 (2001)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. Gul, F., Pesendorfer, W.: A simple theory of temptation and self-control. Princeton University, Mimeo (2005)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Kochov, A.S.: Subjective states without the completeness axiom. University of Rochester, Mimeo (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Kopylov, I.: Perfectionism and choice. Econometrica 80, 1819–1843 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. Kreps, D.M.: A representation theorem for “preference for flexibility,”. Econometrica 47, 565–577 (1979)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  25. Mehta, G.: Topological ordered spaces and utility functions. Int. Econ. Rev. 18, 779–782 (1977)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Nachbin, L.: Topology and Order. Van Nostrand, Princeton (1965)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Ortoleva, P.: The price of flexibility: towards a theory of thinking aversion. J. Econ. Theory 148, 903–934 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  28. Pejsachowicz, L., Toussaert, S.: Choice deferral, indecisiveness and preference for flexibility. J. Econ. Theory 170, 417–425 (2017)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  29. Puppe, C.: An axiomatic approach to “preference for freedom of choice,”. J. Econ. Theory 68, 174–199 (1996)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  30. Saito, K.: Impure altruism and impure selfishness. J. Econ. Theory 158, 336–370 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. Sarver, T.: Anticipating regret: why fewer options may be better. Econometrica 76, 263–305 (2008)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Özgür Evren .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Evren, Ö. (2020). Preference for Flexibility: A Continuous Representation in an Ordinal Setup. In: Bosi, G., Campión, M., Candeal, J., Indurain, E. (eds) Mathematical Topics on Representations of Ordered Structures and Utility Theory. Studies in Systems, Decision and Control, vol 263. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34226-5_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics