Skip to main content

Noble Promises: Performativity and Physiology in Nietzsche

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Life After Literature

Part of the book series: Numanities - Arts and Humanities in Progress ((NAHP,volume 12))

  • 210 Accesses

Abstract

In his treatise On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche elaborates some cardinal aspects of a theory of linguistic performativity, which links language to physiological dimensions. These dimensions are effects of linguistic acts, but also outcomes of a deeper biologic-cultural inheritance of humanity. Linguistic mnemonic techniques and the promise put themselves mutually into effect and reveal their physiological background humanising and dehumanising the human being. The major focus of this paper is directed at the relationship between the performativity of language and its physiological, but also “divine” (pre)conditions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As Werner Hamacher puts it, “In the promise, the promise promises itself, the fact that it is a promise” (1998: 66). Nietzsche stands here on Kantian grounds. The promise already appears as a paradigmatic case or act of morality and is related to the will, already in Grundlegung der Metaphysik der Sitten. At the same time, these passages from On the Genealogy of Morality engage in an implicit dialogue with Kant’s reflections on morality. Cf.: 1998: 65–66.

  2. 2.

    As is well known, Kant put this in the form of the categorical imperative. (“Act as if the maxim of your action were to become through your will a Universal Law of Nature”). See also: Gadamer 1987: 181. The categorical imperative excludes exception: 179.

  3. 3.

    Hamacher 1998: 100. As is well known, Heidegger interpreted Nietzsche’s thought and its place in the history of philosophy as a metaphysics of the will to will. (Nietzsches Wort ‘Gott ist tot’. Heidegger 2003: 234). This, of course, can also be challenged (cf. Henning Ottmann 1987: 358; Hamacher 1998: 108.) on the basis of the present context too.

  4. 4.

    See also: the First Essay of On the Genealogy of Morality: “And just as the common people separates lightning from its flash and takes the latter to be a deed, something performed by a subject, which is called lightning, popular morality separates strength from the manifestations of strength, as though there were an indifferent substratum behind the strong person which had the freedom to manifest strength or not. But there is no such substratum; there is no ‘being’ behind the deed, its effect and what becomes of it; ‘the doer’ is invented as an afterthought,—the doing is everything. Basically, the common people double a deed; when they see lightning, they make a doing-a-deed out of it: they posit the same event, first as cause and then as its effect.” (26).

  5. 5.

    “…den Menschen des eignen unabhängigen langen Willens, der [this “der” may bear to “Mensch” as well as to the “Wille”] versprechen darf…” Nietzsche 1887: 293.

  6. 6.

    Cf. Derrida 1997: 98.

  7. 7.

    An essay by Volker Gerhardt brings these into harmony, arguing that “‘Active forgetfulness’ disciplines man into an active and reliable creature” (Gerhardt 2011: 252). I would say that, on the contrary, it is not so much forgetfulness, but rather the mnemonic technique of forgetfulness that disciplines man. Gerhardt emphasizes all through the importance of the individual, and the reliability of man realized in the promise. The irony of Nietzsche’s text (especially in the pseudo-hymnic passages on the sovereign individual) goes unnoticed in Gerhardt’s smoothing, levelling, stabilizing interpretation. Ottmann misreads this passage in the same way, not paying attention to the irony, or at least, the ambiguity of the text (1987: 212). Cf., on the other hand, the literary scholar, Hamacher’s rigorous interpretation (1998: 85–86). Kai Behrens mentions the “figurality” of the semantics of the “moralized mnemonic technique” in the text (2005: 110). For certain rhetorical effects of the text, see: 164–168.

  8. 8.

    “Each living being can become healthy, strong, and fertile only within a horizon” (Nietzsche 1998: 5). Cf. also Günter Figal’s interpretation: 1999: 58–59.

  9. 9.

    Cf. also Borsche 1992: 307.

  10. 10.

    “There is only a perspectival seeing, only a perspectival ‘knowing;’ the more affects we are able to put into words about a thing, the more eyes, various eyes we are able to use for the same thing, the more complete will be our ‘concept’ of the thing, our ‘objectivity’” (2007: 13).

  11. 11.

    See Deleuze 2006.

  12. 12.

    Nietzsche probably borrows the term “plastic power” from Jacob Burckhardt, who uses it to describe the culture of the Italian Renaissance: “Finally, these intellectual giants, these representatives of the Renaissance, show, in respect to religion, a quality that is common in youthful natures: they distinguish keenly between good and evil, yet they are conscious of no sin. They believe that every disturbance to their inward harmony will be resolved by virtue of their own plastic resources, and therefore they feel no repentance. Thus the need for salvation became weaker, while the ambitions and the intellectual activity of the present either shut out altogether every thought of a world to come, or caused it to assume a poetic instead or a dogmatic form.” (1960: 252). See: Kittsteiner 1996: 56. The essay, despite its title, does not deal with forgetfulness. Cf. also: Figal 1999: 52–53, 265. On the Nietzsche-Burckhardt relation, see also: Ottmann 1987: 18–21, 48–51. On Nietzsche’s notion of the “Renaissance” see ibid. 281–292).

  13. 13.

    See on the notion of the “afformative” as a pre-performative Hamacher 1994: 340–374.

  14. 14.

    Nietzsche often evokes this idea of the secondariness of consciousness in various forms. For example, according to a pseudo-genealogical passage of The Gay Science—which also clarifies the causes of the present self-annihilation of the West—consciousness comes into being as an organ for reading “signs,” as dependent upon, or as an index of communication: “consciousness has developed only under the pressure of the need for communication […] Man, like every living being, thinks continually without knowing it; the thinking that rises to consciousness is only the smallest part of all this-the most superficial and worst part-for only this conscious thinking takes the form of words, which is to say signs of communication, and this fact uncovers the origin of consciousness.” Nietzsche 1974: 298–299. He varies this thought on a vital-physiological level as the origin of morality in a notebook entry: “All intensification (Erhöhung) of life increases (steigert) the communicative power of man and his understanding power too. Our empathy with other souls does not originally mean anything moral, but only the physiological stimulatability involved in mesmerism: ‘sympathy’ or what is called ‘altruism’ are only the products of a psychomotor connection generally understood as belonging to the spirit (Ch. Féré calls this induction psycho-motrice). We never communicate thoughts, but rather movements, mimic signs that we read retrospectively (zurückgelesen), having considered the thoughts.” (Nietzsche 188789: 297).

  15. 15.

    Cf. Tomasello 2014.

  16. 16.

    Ibid. 46, 87–88. Tomasello does not deal with the promise.

  17. 17.

    As Derrida also makes it clear: “There is no ethics without the presence of the other but also, and consequently, without absence, dissimulation, detour, différance, writing. The arche-writing is the origin of morality as of immorality. The nonethical opening of ethics. A violent opening. As in the case of the vulgar concept of writing, the ethical instance of violence must be rigorously suspended in order to repeat the genealogy of morals.” (Derrida 1997: 139–140).

  18. 18.

    Cf. Ottmann 1987: 266. This has been already anticipated in On the Uses and Abuses of History, “For since we are now the products of earlier generations, we are also the products of their aberrations, passions, mistakes, and even crimes. It is impossible to loose oneself from this chain entirely. When we condemn that confusion and consider ourselves released from it, then we have not overcome the fact that we are derived from it. In the best case, we bring the matter to a conflict between our inherited customary nature and our knowledge, in fact, even to a war between a new strict discipline and how we have been brought up and what we have inherited from time immemorial. We cultivate a new habit, a new instinct, a second nature, so that the first nature atrophies”. Nietzsche 1998: 270.

  19. 19.

    The last sentence of the book applies this to the rhetorics of scientific discourse too: “These are all coordinative phenomena through and through, and it is almost inconceivable that they arose evolutionarily from some nonsocial source. Something like the shared intentionality hypothesis just must be true.” A hypothesis that must be “true,” is certainly not a hypothesis, but “the truth” (declared by the same “authoritative voice,” analyzed some pages earlier).

  20. 20.

    Nietzsche replaces “selection” by “interpretation:” “The will to power interprets: there is interpretation in the constitution of an organ. This will determines and separates the levels, the differences in power. The differences of power, however, would not be able to see themselves as such: there must be a being willing to develop, which interprets each other being willing to develop considering its value. […] In fact, interpretation is itself a method to surrender something else. (Organic processes require constant interpretation).” (188587: 139–140).

  21. 21.

    Cf. Ottmann 1987: 229; Figal 199: 247–251.

  22. 22.

    Nietzsche 1874: 362–363. Kaufmann 2013: 228–256. (“Sublimation, Geist and Eros.”) We have to note here that sublimation, in Nietzsche, means stimulation or intensification not devoid of the semantics of the forcification of agonality. Cf. Schluchter 1996: 154–155.

  23. 23.

    The text enumerates the metaphors of violent inscription and dismemberment at length.

  24. 24.

    These are Hamacher’s terms (1998: 83).

  25. 25.

    Ibid.

  26. 26.

    The Birth of Tragedy equally makes a distinction between music and its manifestation, the will.

  27. 27.

    As is well established, Plessner described the ontological mode of being as “excentric positionality” among others, where “excentric” still remains an adjective next to the noun, “positionality.” Heidegger speaks about an “ex-istent,” “ec-static” mode of being, which, just like the often discussed “Da” and “Dasein,” cannot be reduced to the concept of positionality.

  28. 28.

    Heidegger 2010: 322–324.

  29. 29.

    Cf. Simmel 1907: 248–250. (The last chapter of the book is titled “Die Moral der Vornehmheit,” “The Moral of Nobility.”).

  30. 30.

    Nietzsche 1887: 325. In these sentences resonates Burckhardt’s doctrine about the moral in the Renaissance: “The awakening of the conscience was by no means necessarily followed by the sense of sin and the need for salvation (…) but this contempt for repentance must automatically extend to the sphere of morals, because its origin, namely the consciousness of individual force, is universal.” 1960: 279.

  31. 31.

    Nietzsche 1887: 325–326. Or put more theoretically: “All instincts which are not discharged outwardly turn inwards—this is what I call the internalization of man: with it there now evolves in man what will later be called his ‘soul’” (Nietzsche 2007: 57); Nietzsche 1887: 322.

  32. 32.

    And Nietzsche goes on to say, as if anticipating Freud, “This secret self-violation, this artist’s cruelty, this desire to give form to oneself as a piece of difficult, resisting, suffering matter, to brand it with a will, a critique, a contradiction, a contempt, a ‘no,’ this uncanny, terrible but joyous labor of a soul voluntarily split within itself, which makes itself suffer out of the pleasure of making suffer, this whole active ‘bad conscience’” (2007: 59).

  33. 33.

    See: Derek Bickerton’s warning in Bickerton 2009: 5. 26–27. See also: Agamben 2011: 68.

  34. 34.

    On hypnosis, as included in structures of normal perception, on the relationship between hypnoses and automatisms, on the problematisation of rationalist and voluntarist concepts of subjecthood, and on the cultural techniques of hypnotic trance in the second half of the 19th century, see: Crary 1999: 65–72.

  35. 35.

    At one point in the third essay of The Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche contrasts Plato with Homer: “Plato versus Homer: that is complete, genuine antagonism—on the one hand, the sincerest ‘advocate of the beyond,’ the great slanderer of life, on the other hand, its involuntary idolater, the golden nature” (2007: 117). We should pay attention to the literal antagonism between “greatest benevolence” and “involuntary.” (Cf. Simon 2016: 14–29).

  36. 36.

    Cf. Derrida 2011.

  37. 37.

    Nietzsche’s other aphoristic remark can point to a more basic meaning: “We have already gone beyond whatever we have words for.” (“Wofür wir Worte haben, darüber sind wir auch schon hinaus.”) (1889: 128).

  38. 38.

    Speech act theory only reaches this established, determined, authorized level of the promise “I confine my discussion to full blown explicit promises and ignore promises made by elliptical turns of phrase, hints, metaphors, etc. I also ignore promises made in the course of uttering sentences which contain elements irrelevant to the making of the promise. I am also dealing only with categorical promises and ignoring hypothetical promises, for if we get an account of categorical promises it can easily be extended to deal with hypothetical ones. In short, I am going to deal only with a simple and idealized case.” Searle 1969: 55–56. Derrida was right to claim that “I am convinced that speech act theory is fundamentally and in its most fecund, most rigorous, and most interesting aspects […] a theory of right or law, of convention, of political ethics or of politics as ethics” Derrida 1988: 97. For the concept of “making explicit,” and its role in speech act theory, see Campe 2005: 17–39. For Searle’s theory of the promise cf. Wolf 2005: 41–56. In this sense, Searle’ concept of commitment presupposes and inscribes a kind of institutionally supplemented perlocution into the mode of being of the promise, dependent upon the other’s counter-signature.

  39. 39.

    Schneider 2005: 12. While Hobbes equated this force making the promise with the will, Nietzsche does not make such an equation, according to Schneider.

  40. 40.

    Or, as Derrida puts it before Agamben: “An oath is a bond in human language that the human tongue, as such, insofar as it is human, cannot loosen. In human language is a bond stronger than human language. More than man in man. In human language, the element of translation is an inflexible law that at once prohibits the translation of the transaction but commands respect for the original literalness or the given word. It is a law that presides over translation while commanding absolute respect, without any transaction, for the word given in its original letter. The oath, the sworn faith, the act of swearing is transcendence itself, the experience of passing beyond man, the origin of the divine or, if one prefers, the divine origin of the oath. […] When I swear, I swear in a language that no human language has the power to make me abjure, to disrupt, that is to say, to make me perjure myself. The oath passes through language, but it passes beyond human language.” (2001: 185). For the Ancient Greek use and conceptual history of the oath, see: Marót 1924. With regard to Austin, see also: Kulcsár-Szabó 2017: 95–122.

  41. 41.

    Paul de Man famously rewrote Heidegger’s main “thesis” with a Freudian accent: “Die Sprache verspricht (sich).” see “Promises” in Allegories of Reading.

  42. 42.

    Nietzsche was also the philosopher of affirmation (Ja-sagen).

  43. 43.

    Here, language comes into play as the correlative or metaphor of action, or else, as the metonymy (spectre) of action.

References

  • Agamben, Giorgio. 2011. The Sacrament of Language. An Archaeology of the Oath. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behrens, Kai. 2005. Ästhetische Obliviologie. Zur Theoriegeschichte des Vergessens. Würzburg: Königshausen u. Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickerton, Derek. 2009. Adam’s Tongue. How Humans Made Language, How Language Made Humans. New York: Hill & Wang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borsche, Tilman. 1992. Was etwas ist. Fragen nach der Wahrheit der Bedeutung bei Platon, Augustin, Nikolaus von Kues und Nietzsche. Munich: Wilhelm Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burckhardt, Jacob. 1960. The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy. The translation of S. G. C. Middlemore, revised and ed. Irene Gordon, New York: New American Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campe, Rüdiger. 2005. Making it Explicit. Don Giovannis Versprechen oder eine Vorgeschichte des Sprechakts bei Austin. In Die Ordnung des Versprechens, ed. Manfred Schneider, 17–39. Munich: Wilhelm Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crary, Jonathan. 1999. Suspensions of Perception. Attention, Spectacle, and Modern Culture. Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles. 2006. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Man, Paul. 1979. Allegories of Reading. Promises. New Haven/London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1988. Limited Inc. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1997. Of Grammatology. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 2001. What Is a ‘Relevant’ Translation? Critical Inquiry 27: 174–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 2011. The Beast and the Sovereign I. Seminar 2001–2002. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Figal, Günter. 1999. Nietzsche. Eine philosophische Einführung. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1987. Über die Möglichkeit einer philosophischen Ethik. In Gesammelte Werke 4, 175–188. Tübingen: Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerhardt, Volker. 2011. “Das Thier, das versprechen darf” Mensch, Gesellschaft und Politik bei Friedrich Nietzsche. In Die Funken des freien Geistes: neuere Aufsätze zu Nietzsches Philosophie der Zukunft., eds. Jan-Christoph Heilinger and Nikolaos Loukidelis, 243–260. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamacher, Werner. 1998. Das Versprechen der Auslegung. Zum hermeneutischen Imperativ bei Kant und Nietzsche. In: Entferntes Verstehen. Studien zu Philosophie und Literatur von Kant bis Celan. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamacher, Werner. 1994. Afformativ, Streik. In Was heißt ‚Darstellen’?, ed. Christiaan L. Hart-Nibbrig, 340–374. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2003. Holzwege. GA 5. Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2010. Being and Time (trans: Joan Stanbaugh). Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, Walter. 2013. Nietzsche. Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kittsteiner, Heinz-Dieter. 1996. Erinnern – Vergessen – Orientieren. Nietzsches Begriff des ‘umhüllenden Wahns’ als geschichtsphilosophische Kategorie. In “Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Historie für das Leben”. Nietzsche und die Erinnerung in der Moderne, ed. Dieter Borchmeyer, 48–75. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulcsár-Szabó, Zoltán. 2017. Austin és a Hippolütosz [Austin and the Hippolytus]. Irodalomtörténet 1: 95–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marót, Karl. 1924. Der Eid als Tat. In Acta Litterarum ac Scientiarum Regiae Universitatis Francisco-Iosephinae sect. philol.-hist., tom. I fasc. 1, Szeged, 1–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1874. Schopenhauer als Erzieher. In KSA 1, 335–427.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1878. Menschliches, Allzumenschliches I. In KSA 2, 9–366.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1880–82. Nachgelassene Fragmente 1880–1882 (KSA 9).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1881. Morgenröthe. Gedanken über die moralischen Vorurtheile. In KSA 3, 9–331.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1884–85. Nachgelassene Fragmente 1884–1885 (KSA 11).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1885–87. Nachgelassene Fragmente 1885–1887 (KSA 12).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1887–89. Nachgelassene Fragmente 1887–1889 (KSA 13).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1887. Zur Genealogie der Moral. In KSA 5, 245–412.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1889. Götzendämmerung. Streifzüge eines Unzeitgemässen. In KSA 6, 55–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1911. The Dawn of Day (trans: J. M. Kennedy). London: T.N. Foulis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1974. The Gay Science (With a Prelude in Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs) (trans: Walter Kaufmann). London: Penguin Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1988. Sämtliche Werke. Kritische Studienausgabe (KSA), eds. Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari. München/Berlin/New York: dtv/De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1996. Human, All Too Human, A book for free spirits (trans: R. J. Hollingdale). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1998. On the Use and Abuse of History for Life (trans: Ian C. Johnston). British Columbia: Liberal Studies Department Malaspina University-College Nanaimo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 2007. On the Genealogy of Morality, ed. Keith Ansell-Pearson (trans: Carol Diethe). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ottmann, Henning. 1987. Philosophie und Politik bei Nietzsche. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schluchter, Wolfgang. 1996. Zeitgemäße Unzeitgemäße. Von Friedrich Nietzsche über Georg Simmel zu Max Weber. In “Vom Nutzen und Nachteil der Historie für das Leben: Nietzsche und die Erinnerung in der Moderne, ed. Dieter Borchmeyer, 146–166. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, Manfred. 2005. Vorwort. In Die Ordnung des Versprechens, ed. Manfred Schneider, 9–16. Munich: Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. 1969. Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simmel, Georg. 1907. Schopenhauer und Nietzsche. Leipzig/Munich: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, Attila. 2016. Platón és az enthusiasmos médiapolitikája [Plato and the Media Politics of enthusiasmos]. Ókor 3: 14–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, Michael. 2014. A Natural History of Human Thinking. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Humboldt, Wilhelm. 1979. Über die Verschiedenheit des menschlichen Sprachbaues und ihren Einfluß auf die geistige Entwicklung des Menschengeschlechts. In Schriften zur Sprachphilosophie, ed. I.I.I. Werke. Stuttgart: Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, Eckard. 2005. Das Versprechen der Sprechakttheorie. In Die Ordnung des Versprechens, ed. Manfred Schneider, 41–56. Munich: Wilhelm Fink.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Csongor Lőrincz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Lőrincz, C. (2020). Noble Promises: Performativity and Physiology in Nietzsche. In: Kulcsár-Szabó, Z., Lénárt, T., Simon, A., Végső, R. (eds) Life After Literature. Numanities - Arts and Humanities in Progress, vol 12. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-33738-4_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics