Skip to main content

Internal Senses and Aristotle’s Cognitive Theory

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Internal Senses in the Aristotelian Tradition

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 22))

  • 225 Accesses

Abstract

The question I plan to address is: Does Aristotle posit one or more internal senses in theorizing about perception and other types of sensory experience? My initial thought is that there are good reasons to be skeptical.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a critical analysis of the argument for this claim in De Anima 2.3, see C. Shields, comm. 2016.

  2. 2.

    It is precisely this dependence upon a concurrent perception of an external object that accounts for the morally pernicious effects of pleasure and pain. Too much pleasure associated with flavors is implicated in gluttony; too much pain associated with the sights and sounds of an approaching hostile army is implicated in cowardice.

  3. 3.

    For a succinct thumbnail sketch of this construal of the common sense, see P. Gregoric, (2007) pp. 9–13.

  4. 4.

    Modrak (1987) chapter six.

  5. 5.

    For present purposes, treating dream phantasmata as images is unproblematic. Granted, there has been considerable discussion of the broader question of whether phantasmata are images in the secondary literature. See Modrak (1986) and Modrak, chapter four (1987); for more recent contributions to this discussion, see Scheiter (2012) and Radovic (forthcoming).

  6. 6.

    Aristotle also mentions the metaphorical use of phantasia only to set it aside in 3.3. There is no evidence that when Aristotle appeals to phantasia in other places that he is using the term metaphorically.

  7. 7.

    Even phantasia is true in the case of proper objects when perception is also present, but it need not be in the absence of a concurrent perception (3.3.428b27–30).

  8. 8.

    See, e.g., Nussbaum, (1978) pp. 223–321. Conceiving phantasia as appearances has prompted other commentators to downplay the role of imagery in it. See, e.g. Schofield (1978) p. 102. See also Scheiter (2012) and Radovic (forthcoming).

  9. 9.

    For a detailed defense of the Sensory Content Analysis of phantasia, see Modrak (1986) and Modrak (1987).

  10. 10.

    See, for a different interpretation of the canonical account, M. Wedin (1988), chap. 2, which argues for the functional incompleteness of phantasia.

  11. 11.

    Cf. Schofield (1978) which characterizes Aristotle’s conception of imagination in 3.3 as non-paradigmatic sensory experience.

References

  • Gregoic, P. (2007). Aristotle on the common sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, G., & Owen, G. (Eds.). (1978). Aristotle on mind and the senses: Proceedings of the seventh symposium Aristotelicum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modrak, D. (1986). Phantasia Reconsidered. In Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie. Band 1986. Heft 1, 47–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Modrak, D. (1987). Aristotle: The power of perception. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1978). Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radovic, F. (Forthcoming). Eidola, phantasmata and images in Aristotle.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheiter, K. M. (2012). Images, appearances and Phantasia in Aristotle. Phronesis, 57, 251–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, M. (1978). In G. Lloyd & G. Owen (Eds.), Aristotle on the imagination.” Aristotle on mind and the senses (pp. 249–277). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shields, C. (2016). Aristotle De Anima. Translation with introduction and commentary. Oxford: University of Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedin, M. (1988). Mind and imagination in Aristotle. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Deborah Modrak .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Modrak, D. (2020). Internal Senses and Aristotle’s Cognitive Theory. In: Mousavian, S., Fink, J. (eds) The Internal Senses in the Aristotelian Tradition. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 22. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-33408-6_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics