Skip to main content

Model Types and Explanatory Styles in Cognitive Theories

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology (MBR 2018)

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 49))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 399 Accesses

Abstract

In this paper we argue that the debate between representational and anti-representational cognitive theories cannot be reduced to a difference between the types of model respectively employed. We show that, on the one side, models standardly used in representational theories, such as computational ones, can be analyzed in the context of dynamical systems theory and, on the other, non-representational theories such as Gibson’s ecological psychology can be formalized with the use of computational models. Given these considerations, we propose that the true conceptual difference between representational and anti-representational cognitive descriptions should be characterized in terms of style of explanation, which indicates the particular stance taken by a theory with respect to its explanatory target.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Beer (1998) for a reply to van Gelder (1998) on this point.

  2. 2.

    An example is a dynamical system DS in which any state transition moves the system to a fixed point. Let the time set T of DS be the set of reals, and its state space M be any finite or countably infinite set. Let \(y \in M\) be a fixed point, that is to say, a state y such that, for any t, \(g^{t}(y) = y\). The state transitions of DS are then defined as follows. Let \(y \in M\); for any \(t \ne 0\), for any state \(x \in M\), \(g^{t}(x) = y\); \(g^{0}\) is the identity function on M.

  3. 3.

    See, e.g., Fodor (1980).

  4. 4.

    The main components of a TM are the following:

    1. 1.

      a finite automaton (Minsky 1967; Wells 2005) consisting of

      • a simple input-output device that implements a specific set of instructions (machine table);

      • an internal memory that holds only one discrete element at each step (internal state) and

      • an internal device (read/write head) that can scan and change the content of the internal memory.

    2. 2.

      An external memory consisting of a tape divided into squares, potentially extendible in both directions ad infinitum;

    3. 3.

      an external device (read/write/move head) that scans the content of a cell at a time and allows the finite automaton to work on the memory tape.

  5. 5.

    This view is also consistent with Wilson’s proposal of a wide computationalism (Wilson 1994).

  6. 6.

    The authors define the concept of duality as follows: “[A] duality relation between two structures X and Z is specified by any symmetrical rule, operation, transformation or ‘mapping’, T, where T applies to map X onto Z and Z onto X: that is, where \(T(X) \rightarrow Z\) and \(T(Z) \rightarrow X\) such that for any relation \(r_{1}\) in X, there exist some relation \(r_{2}\) in Z such that \(T: r_{1} \rightarrow r_{2}\) and \(T: r_{2} \rightarrow r_{1}\); hence, \(X R Z = Z R X\) under transformation T” (Shaw and Turvey 1981, p. 381). They also highlight the importance of this concept in logic, mathematics and geometry, showing as examples dualities in logic between DeMorgan laws, theorems in point and line geometries, open and closed sets in topology, etc. (Shaw and Turvey 1981, pp. 382–384).

  7. 7.

    In situation theory a constraint is defined as a “dependency relation between situation types” (Greeno 1994, p. 338).

References

  • Beer R (1998) Framing the debate between computational and dynamical approaches to cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci 21:630

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bremner JG (1978) Egocentric versus allocentric spatial coding in nine-month-old infants: factors influencing the choice of code. Dev Psychol 14(4):346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond A (1998) Understanding the a-not-b error: working memory vs. reinforced response, or active trace vs. latent trace. Dev Sci 1(2):185–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1980) Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology. Behav Brain Sci 3(01):63–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T (1995) What might cognition be, if not computation? J Philos 92(7):345–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T (1998) The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci 21:615–665

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J (1966) The senses considered as perceptual systems. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J (1977) The theory of affordances. In: Shaw R, Bransfordk J (eds) Perceiving, acting, and knowing, toward an ecological psychology. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson J (1979) The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Giunti M (1995) Dynamical models of cognition. In: Port R, van Gelder T (eds) Mind as motion. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 71–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Giunti M, Pinna S (2016) For a dynamical approach to human computation. Logic J IGPL 24(4):557–569

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greeno J (1994) Gibson’s affordances. Psychol Rev 101:336–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso JAS (1995) Dynamic patterns: the self-organization of brain and behavior. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Minsky ML (1967) Computation, finite and infinite machines. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs

    Google Scholar 

  • Munakata Y (1998) Infant perseveration and implications for object permanence theories: a PDP model of the AB task. Dev Sci 1(2):161–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J (1952) The origins of intelligence in children. International Universities Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinna S (2017) Extended cognition and the dynamics of algorithmic skills. Springer, Cham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Port R, van Gelder T (eds) (1995) Mind as motion. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaw R, Turvey M (1981) Coalitions as models for ecosystems: a realist perspective on perceptual organization. In: Kubovy M, Pomerantz J (eds) Perceptual organization. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith L, Thelen E (eds) (1993) A dynamic systems approach to development. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith L, Thelen E, Titzer R, McLin D (1999) Knowing in the context of acting: the task dynamics of the A-not-B error. Psychol Rev 106:235–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith LB, Thelen E (2003) Development as a dynamic system. Trends Cogn Sci 7(8):343–348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thelen E, Smith L (eds) (1994) A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tschacher W, Dauwalder J (eds) (2003) The dynamical systems approach to cognition. World Scientific, Singapore

    Google Scholar 

  • Turvey M (1992) Affordances and prospective control: an outline of the ontology. Ecol Psychol 4:173–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T (1999) Dynamic approaches to cognition. In: Wilson RA, Keil FC (eds) The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 244–246

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder T, Port R (1995) It’s about time: an overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In: Port R, van Gelder T (eds) Mind as motion. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wells A (1998) Turing’s analysis of computation and theories of cognitive architecture. Cogn Sci 22:269–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wells A (2002) Gibson’s affordances and Turing’s theory of computation. Ecol Psychol 14:140–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wells A (2005) Rethinking cognitive computation: Turing and the science of the mind. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RA (1994) Wide computationalism. Mind 103(411):351–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work is supported by Fondazione di Sardegna and Regione Autonoma della Sardegna, research project “Science and its Logics: the Representation’s Dilemma,” Cagliari, CUP F72F16003220002.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Simone Pinna .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Pinna, S., Giunti, M. (2019). Model Types and Explanatory Styles in Cognitive Theories. In: Nepomuceno-Fernández, Á., Magnani, L., Salguero-Lamillar, F., Barés-Gómez, C., Fontaine, M. (eds) Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. MBR 2018. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 49. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-32722-4_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics