Skip to main content

The Battle for Free Will

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Divine Omniscience and Human Free Will

Part of the book series: Palgrave Frontiers in Philosophy of Religion ((PFPR))

  • 329 Accesses

Abstract

The aim of this chapter is to introduce the reader to the dilemma of foreknowledge and human freedom. We present first the logical version of the problem—which dates back to Aristotle’s De Interpretatione—and then the theological version—which is the main theme of this book. We cast some light on the notions of logical fatalism, determinism and the interplay between truth and necessity. We then offer an analysis of the concept of bivalence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    One may wonder whether future contingents that do not depend on the free action of human beings may exist. We will deal later with this issue.

  2. 2.

    Zagzebski, Linda, “Foreknowledge and Free Will”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/free-will-foreknowledge/.

  3. 3.

    A necessitist universe should not be confused with a necessary universe; the latter is as it is and cannot be otherwise. On the contrary, it is strictly contingent that a necessitist universe has got that particular structure.

  4. 4.

    Put in more technical terms, we affirm that these universes dictate the existence of convergent histories and, consequently, the branching also towards the past. As we shall see in the book, there are valid reasons to consider such structures as problematic.

  5. 5.

    Readers will forgive us for such an unorthodox version of Aristotle’s naval battle.

  6. 6.

    See Bernstein (2002, p. 70).

  7. 7.

    Øhrstrøm and Hasle (2007, pp. 6–114) and Crivelli (2004, ch. 7) are great starting points.

  8. 8.

    Proposition and sentence are often used in literature with two different meanings: the term “sentences” refers to linguistic entities, while the term “propositions” refers to the meaning of these entities. As this distinction is not relevant for the aims of this book, we will not follow this convention: we will be very sloppy in using these two terms, which are to be considered as synonymous in this book except in some particular cases, apparent from the context, in which we come back to the traditional distinction between these two terms.

  9. 9.

    In this introductory chapter, we tried to limit the logic symbols. However, some exceptions have to be made. As we have stated in the Preface, the use of logic-mathematical models should help clarify the instances at stake.

  10. 10.

    It is a mere introduction of disjunction: if ψ follows from φ, then from φ follows that ψ ∨ θ, where θ is any closed formula. The correctness of this rule can be easily recognized if we consider that the truth of a disjunct is enough to make the disjunction true.

  11. 11.

    As we shall see in Chap. 2 and following, the semantics of future tensed propositions are crucial to understand the issues of foreknowledge and free will.

  12. 12.

    The philosophical tradition dates back to Aristotle the first formulation of such a view, which is called the correspondence theory of truth. Since the concept of correspondence is rather demanding from a theoretical point of view, we will call this view the classical conception of truth.

  13. 13.

    Two seminal papers on the concept of truth-makers are Mulligan et al. (1984) and Fox (1987). A locus classicus is Armstrong (2004). An excellent collection is Lowe and Rami (2014). In Sect. 4.5.1 we will thoroughly deal with the issue.

  14. 14.

    Many other views can be interpreted as more or less sophisticated specifications of the two above-mentioned main strategies.

  15. 15.

    Understanding which strategy Aristotle has really endorsed is a vexata quaestio. Standard view is that Aristotle rethought the extension of the principle of bivalence. But there are positions contrary to it. For an overview, Crivelli (2004).

  16. 16.

    Again, this passage is guaranteed by the fact that if the proposition p is true, then also the proposition p ∨¬p is true; analogously, in the scenarios where ¬p is true, the proposition p ∨¬p is also true.

  17. 17.

    And this possibility has been discussed by Freddoso (1983), Mavrodes (1984), Forrest (1985), Talbott (1986) and Reichenbach (1987).

  18. 18.

    Here we assume that divine properties such as omniscience are necessary; the case of a God only contingently omniscient or choosing not to be omniscient is not accounted for. Some scholars proposed similar solutions: see, for instance, Kreiner (1997, ch. 3).

  19. 19.

    It is a very plausible logical principle. It is particularly easy to understand if we use a possible words semantic where \( \square r \) means that r is true in all possible worlds. If r is true in all possible worlds and it is also true in all possible worlds that r → s, then it is true in all possible worlds that s, by modus ponens. But, in this semantic, the fact that s is true in all possible worlds means that s is necessary.

  20. 20.

    For two replies to Warfield’s argument, see Hasker (1998) and Brueckner (2000). They both differ from the criticism we will illustrate here.

  21. 21.

    This does not deny the close affinity between the two arguments and that the solutions to logical and theological fatalism have something in common.

  22. 22.

    Of course, there are tons of other problems of the philosophical and theological kind connected to such topics. For instance, the modality of God’s knowledge. A frequent criticism claims that the modality by which God knows is not propositional, rather He benefits from a sort of direct intuition (Alston 1986). We are not going to investigate this issue; nonetheless, we think that, with some adjustments and corrections, our analysis can be applied to a conception of that kind.

References

  • Alston, W.P. 1986. Does god have beliefs? Religious Studies 22(3–4): 287–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. 2004. Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, M. 2002. Fatalism. In The Oxford handbook of free will, ed. R. Kane, 65–81. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner, A. 2000. On an attempt to demonstrate the compatibility of divine foreknowledge and human freedom. Faith and Philosophy 17(1): 132–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crivelli, P. 2004. Aristotle on truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Laplace, P.S. 1902. A philosophical essay on probabilities. London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. 1964. Bringing about the past. The Philosophical Review 73(3): 338–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. 1985. Backward causation in defence of free will. Mind 94(374): 210–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, J.F. 1987. Truthmaker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65(2): 188–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freddoso, A.J. 1983. Accidental necessity and logical determinism. The Journal of Philosophy 80(5): 257–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hasker, W. 1998. God, time, and knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kreiner, A. 1997. Gott im Leid: Zur Stichhaltigkeit der Theodizee-Argumente. New York: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, J.E., and A. Rami. 2014. Truth and truth-making. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mavrodes, G.I. 1984. Is the past unpreventable? Faith and Philosophy 1(2): 131–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, K., P. Simons, and B. Smith. 1984. Truth-makers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44(3): 287–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Øhrstrøm, P., and P. Hasle. 2007. Temporal logic: From ancient ideas to artificial intelligence, vol. 57. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, B. 1987. Hasker on omniscience. Faith and Philosophy 4(1): 86–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Talbott, T.B. 1986. On divine foreknowledge and bringing about the past. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46(3): 455–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warfield, T.A. 1997. Divine foreknowledge and human freedom are compatible. Noûs 31(1): 80–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L.T. 1991. The dilemma of freedom and foreknowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. 2002. Omniscience and the arrow of time. Faith and Philosophy 19(4): 503–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ciro De Florio .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

De Florio, C., Frigerio, A. (2019). The Battle for Free Will. In: Divine Omniscience and Human Free Will. Palgrave Frontiers in Philosophy of Religion. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-31300-5_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics