Skip to main content

Strategic Aspects

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Systems, Procedures and Voting Rules in Context

Abstract

This chapter deals with the concept of manipulation, understood as preference misrepresentation, in the light of the main theoretical results focusing on their practical significance (This chapter is largely based on Nurmi (Transactions on computational collective intelligence XXIII. Springer, Berlin, pp. 149–161, 2016)). Manipulability is a pervasive property among choice rules. However, its practical importance hinges on several things. The information requirements of successful misrepresentation can be very demanding and suitable situations may not be common. We also review some indices measuring the degree of manipulability of choice functions. Moreover, the results on complexity of manipulation as well as on safe manipulability are briefly touched upon.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 29.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    A Nash equilibrium in pure strategies is an n-tuple of strategies (one for each individual) such that no individual is better off deviating from his/her strategy in this n-tuple, provided that the others stick to their strategy choices. So, in Nash equilibrium unilateral deviations do not bring benefit to the deviator. The same idea extends to mixed strategies, i.e. probability distributions over pure strategies. In this work we focus on pure strategies only.

  2. 2.

    With sincere voting the outcome is the worst for the 2 voters, with strategic voting their most preferred alternative wins.

  3. 3.

    It should be mentioned that in the profiles constructed in this work, the number of voters having each preference ranking can be multiplied by any integer without changing the outcomes as long as the same integer is used as the multiplier in all preference rankings. This follows from the homogeneity of nearly all procedures discussed here. The only exception is Dodgson’s rule, but its non-homogeneity is not relevant in the examples discussed in this book.

  4. 4.

    \(K = \sum _{j} J_{j}\).

  5. 5.

    In 3-alternative contexts the threshold rule ranks alternative x ahead of y if and only if the number of individuals giving y the lowest grade is strictly larger than the number of individuals assigning x the lowest grade. In case x and y are given the lowest grade by the same number of individuals, their collective ranking is determined by the number of individuals assigning x and y the middle grade.

References

  • Aleskerov, F. T., Karabekian, D., Sanver, M. R., & Yakuba, V. (2011). On the degree of manipulability of multi-valued social choice rules. Essays in Honor of Hannu Nurmi. Homo Œconomicus, 28, 205–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aleskerov, F. T., Karabekian, D., Sanver, M. R., & Yakuba, V. (2012). On the manipulability of voting rules: The case of 4 and 5 alternatives. Mathematical Social Sciences, 64, 67–73.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Aleskerov, F. T., & Kurbanov, E. (1999). Degree of manipulability of social choice procedures. In A. Alkan, C. Aliprantis, & N. Yannelis (Eds.), Current trends in economics (pp. 13–27). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bartholdi, J. J., III, Tovey, C. A. & Trick, M. A. (1989a). Voting schemes for which it can be difficult to tell who won the election.Social Choice and Welfare, 6, 157–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartholdi, J. J., III, Tovey, C. A., & Trick, M. A. (1989b). The computational difficulty of manipulating an election. Social Choice and Welfare, 6, 227–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. E., & Kelly, J. S. (2015). Anonymous, neutral and strategy-proof rules on the Condorcet domain. Economics Letters, 128, 79–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conitzer, V., & Walsh, T. (2016). Barriers to manipulation. In F. Brandt, V. Conitzer, U. Endriss, J. Lang, & A. D. Procaccia (Eds.), Handbook of computational social choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Farquharson, R. (1969). Theory of voting. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, A., & Serrano, R. (2006). Welfare economics and social choice theory (2nd ed.). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1974). Paradoxes of voting. American Political Science Review, 68, 537–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1981). Inverted orders for monotone voting rules. Discrete Applied Mathematics, 3, 27–36.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C., & Brams, S. (1983). Paradoxes of preferential voting. Mathematics Magazine, 56, 201–214.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1976). Manipulation of social choice functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 217–228.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1973). Manipulation of voting schemes: A general result. Econometrica, 41, 587–601.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hemaspaandra, L., & Ogihara, M. (2002). The complexity theory companion. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, J. S. (1993). Almost all social rules are highly manipulable, but a few aren’t. Social Choice and Welfare, 10, 161–175.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, G. H. (1977). A dynamical model of political equilibrium. Journal of Economic Theory, 16, 310–334.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, A. (2015). Private communication October 11, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1983). Strategy and social choice. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1988). Condorcet’s principle implies the no-show paradox. Journal of Economic Theory, 45, 53–64.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Napel, S. (2015). Private communications October 7–9, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nitzan, S. (1981). Some measures of closeness to unanimity and their implications. Theory and Decision, 13, 129–138.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Nitzan, S. (2010). Collective preference and choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (1984). On taking preferences seriously. In D. Anckar & E. Berndtson (Eds.), Essays on democratic theory. Tampere: Finnpublishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nurmi, H. (2016). Reflections of the significance of misrepresenting preferences. In N. T. Nguyeng, R. Kowalzyk, & J. Mercik (Eds.), Transactions on computational collective intelligence XXIII (pp. 149–161). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pérez, J. (2001). The strong no show paradoxes are a common flaw in Condorcet voting correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 18, 601–616.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Saari, D. G. (2001). Chaotic Elections! A Mathematician Looks at Voting. Providence: American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Satterthwaite, M. (1975). Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s conditions. Journal of Economic Theory, 10, 187–217.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Slinko, A., & White, S. (2014). Is it ever safe to vote strategically? Social Choice and Welfare, 43, 403–427.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, A. D. (2005). Social choice and the mathematics of manipulation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adiel Teixeira de Almeida .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

de Almeida, A.T., Morais, D.C., Nurmi, H. (2019). Strategic Aspects. In: Systems, Procedures and Voting Rules in Context . Advances in Group Decision and Negotiation, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-30955-8_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics