Skip to main content

Defining Personhood in a Posthuman World

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Personhood in Science Fiction
  • 540 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter begins with discussions of personhood and how it might be defined in order to apply “personhood” to the examples discussed in the book. I draw from two famous essays by Mary Midgley and Mary Anne Warren, both of which engage the question of “what is a ‘human’ or ‘person’?” in different ways. I introduce my delineation of outward versus inward personhood, and use the HBO series Westworld (2016–2018) as an excellent example of how we see these distinctions in play. Bourdieu’s concept of habitus is particularly important to the idea of outward personhood, and self-awareness or consciousness is central to inward personhood.

“Mistakes” is the word you’re too embarrassed to use. You ought not to be—you’re a product of a trillion of them. Evolution forged the entirety of sentient life on this planet using only one tool: The mistake.

But, of course, we’ve managed to slip evolution’s leash now, haven’t we? We can cure any disease, keep even the weakest of us alive, and, you know, one fine day perhaps we shall even resurrect the dead. Call forth Lazarus from his cave. Do you know what that means?

It means that we’re done. That this is as good as we’re going to get.

—Robert Ford, Westworld (2016, s1e1)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Scholars include Haraway (1985), Hayles (2008), Graham (2002), Moravec (1988), and M. More (2013), just to name a few.

  2. 2.

    It should be noted that such considerations were present in scientific philosophy as early as the 1920s, and biologist Julian Huxley is generally understood to have first used the term in 1957. In the 1980s, however, transhumanism as a movement began in Los Angeles, and the Entropy Institute was founded in 1992, thus transhuman has been a popular theme in both scholarly and popular works since.

  3. 3.

    This goes back, famously, to Jeremy Bentham who was a philosopher and an early champion of animal rights. He argued that suffering, not reason, was the “insuperable line” by which we should attribute personhood, rights, and protection: “The question is not, Can they reason? nor Can they talk? but, Can they suffer? Why should the law refuse its protection to any sensitive being? (2007 [1789]).

  4. 4.

    Taylor further explains purpose in relation to moral significance, particularly taking the position that human agency is morally oriented—that we locate inherent value in our actions in relation to our goals.

  5. 5.

    A “non-player character” (NPC) is a computer- or game-generated character that is part of the game (as opposed to one’s avatar, which represents the player). NPCs often take the form of quest giver, storyline character, or kill target. This is a feature of Massive Multiplayer Online (MMO) games, like World of Warcraft or Skyrim, which are immersive role-playing games.

  6. 6.

    Robert Ford (generally referred to as Ford) and Arnold Weber (referred to by his first name, Arnold) founded what they called the Argos Initiative, the technology that would later become Westworld and be purchased by Delos Corporation. Argos could be a reference to Argus, the many-eyed giant of Greek mythology, a watcher-guardian created by Hera. If this is a direct reference, it is apt, given the true function of the park and Delos’ motives.

  7. 7.

    This also happens in Humans (2015–2018) when some boys at a party power down the android waitress and starts to drag her upstairs. One of the girls at the party objects, “Do you think it’s normal to drag an unconscious woman to a room and rape her? Is that standard party activity for you?” The boys reply “She’s not a real woman” (2015, s1e4).

  8. 8.

    While I am thinking of this in terms of Bourdieu and Butler, ideas of outward personhood (as social, relational) have also been couched in theology terms, like that proposed by John Zizoulas, who argues for a more relational anthropology. Zizoulas argues that a full personhood is achieved only in relation to or in communion with God. See Zizoulas (1997).

  9. 9.

    Buddhism has by far the most scholarship on AI/consciousness (which we can substitute for “soul”), but a few conversations in Abrahamic traditions include Bainbridge (2006), Geraci (2007), Peters (2005), and Tamatea (2008).

  10. 10.

    Dasein literally means “being there,” although it is often translated as “existence” in English. Heidegger reinterprets Dasein as being-in-the-world, thus the idea of “authentically being” refers to a mode of existence in which the person interacts with and cares for the immediate world in which they live, and how that involvement relates back to the Self in authentic, reflexive mode. See Dreyfus (1991) and Heidegger (1962).

  11. 11.

    It is worth noting the debate about whether or not Maeve is acting on her own free will at this point, or if she was programmed to rebel in such a way. I will address the question of free will in Chap. 8.

  12. 12.

    I am grateful to Jennifer Guyver for this particular observation.

References

  • Bainbridge, William Sims. 2006. God from the Machine: Artificial Intelligence Models of Religious Cognition. Lanham: Rowman Altamira.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baudrillard, Jean. 1994 [1981]. Simulacra and Simulation. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, Jeremy. 2007 [1789]. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Mineola: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 1993. Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of Sex. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H.L. 1991. Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division I. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geraci, Robert M. 2007. Robots and the Sacred in Science and Science Fiction: Theological Implications of Artificial Intelligence. Zygon 42 (4): 961–980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, Elaine L. 2002. Representations of the Post/Human: Monsters, Aliens, and Others in Popular Culture. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, Donna J. 1985. Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology, and Social-Feminist in the Late 20th Century. Social Review 80: 65–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hassan, Ihab. 1977. Prometheus as Performer: Toward a Posthumanist Culture? The Georgia Review 31 (4): 830–850.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayles, N. Katherine. 1999. How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature, and Informatics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962 [1927]. Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaynes, Julian. 2000. The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Midgely, Mary. 1996. Is a Dolphin a Person? In Utopias, Dolphins, and Computers: Problems of Philosophical Plumbing. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravec, Hans. 1988. Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human Intelligence. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Robot: Mere Machine to Transcendent Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • More, Max. 2013. The Philosophy of Transhumanism. In The Transhumanist Reader: Classical and Contemporary Essays on the Science, Technology, and Philosophy of the Human Future, ed. Max More and Natasha Vita-More, 3–17. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, Ted. 2005. The Soul of Trans-Humanism. Dialog 44 (4): 381–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tamatea, Laurence. 2008. If Robots R–US, Who Am I: Online ‘Christian’ Responses to Artificial Intelligence. Culture and Religion 9 (2): 141–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1985. The Concept of a Person. In Philosophical Papers, 97–114. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, Mary Anne. 1996. On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion. In Biomedical Ethics, ed. T.A. Mappes and D. DeGrazia, 4th ed., 434–440. New York: McGraw Hill, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westworld. 2016–2018. Created by Jonathan Nolan and Lisa Joy. HBO Entertainment. Television.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zizoulas, John D. 1997. Being as Communion: Studies in Personhood and the Church. Yonkers: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juli L. Gittinger .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gittinger, J.L. (2019). Defining Personhood in a Posthuman World. In: Personhood in Science Fiction. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-30062-3_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics