Skip to main content

Argument Evaluation in Philosophy: Fallacies as Strategic Maneuvering

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
From Argument Schemes to Argumentative Relations in the Wild

Part of the book series: Argumentation Library ((ARGA,volume 35))

  • 286 Accesses

Abstract

In order to gain a better understanding of philosophical dialogues as critical discussions, this paper focuses on the evaluative strategies that philosophers use in their argumentation, and especially in the charge of committing a fallacy. In order to illustrate some problems with the evaluation of philosophical arguments, the charge of committing a genetic fallacy is analyzed. It is argued that the charge of committing such fallacy could be better understood as a case of strategic maneuvering. Some historical evidence is presented in favor of this grasp by revisiting the controversy given rise to over the genetic fallacy around the nineteen fifties and sixties. An account of charging the other party of committing a genetic fallacy as strategic maneuvering is presented, and some ways in which such maneuver could derail are analyzed. To conclude, some general remarks are made regarding the use of (certain) fallacies in philosophical controversies and some valuable consequences of considering philosophical arguments as strategic maneuvering are stated.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In 1912, speaking about Wittgenstein, Russell writes: “I told him he ought not simply to state what he thinks true, but to give arguments for it, but he said arguments spoil its beauty, and that he would feel as if he was dirtying a flower with muddy hands. … I told him I hadn’t the heart to say anything against that, and that he had better acquire a slave to state the arguments” (Monk, 1996, p. 264).

  2. 2.

    In the history of philosophical ethics, another possibility was considered, namely, the consequences. However, the consideration of consequences as a relevant item in assessing moral principles was also dismissed as a fallacy, as an ad consequentiam fallacy (see Walton, 1999).

  3. 3.

    The idea of effectiveness is however broader than the idea of persuasiveness: “the term effectiveness is not exclusively applicable to argumentative moves made in the argumentation stage (as at least the term persuasiveness is), but also to argumentative moves made in the other dialectical discussion stages (which are not aimed directly at gaining acceptance of a standpoint)” (van Eemeren, Garssen, & Meuffels, 2012, pp. 51–52)

References

  • Boudry, M., Paglieri, F., & Pigliucci, M. (2015). The fake, the flimsy, and the fallacious: Demarcating arguments in real life. Argumentation, 29, 431–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M. R. (1914). History versus value. Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 11, 701–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M. E., & Nagel, E. (1934). An introduction to logic and scientific method. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copi, I. (1980). Introducción a la Lógica. Buenos Aires: Eudeba.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crouch, M. A. (1991). Feminist philosophy and the genetic fallacy. Hypatia, 6, 104–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crouch, M. A. (1993). A limited defense of the genetic fallacy. Metaphilosophy, 24, 227–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1902a). The evolutionary method as applied to morality. Philosophical Review, 11, 107–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1902b). The evolutionary method as applied to morality: II. Its significance for conduct. Philosophical Review, 11, 353–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1928). The inclusive philosophic idea. Monist, 38, 161–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1988). Theory of valuation. In J. Dewey (Ed.), The collected works of John Dewey (Vol. 13, pp. 190–253). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feuer, L. S. (1983). The genetic fallacy re-examined. In P. Kurtz (Ed.), Sidney Hook: Philosopher of democracy and humanism (pp. 227–246). Buffalo: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankena, W. K. (1939). The naturalistic fallacy. Mind, 48, 464–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godden, David M. (2005). Deductivism as an interpretive strategy: A reply to Groarke’s recent defense of reconstructive deductivism. Argumentation and advocacy, 41, 168–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goudge, T. A. (1961). The genetic fallacy. Synthese, 13, 41–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. (1999). Deductivism within pragma-dialectics. Argumentation, 13, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1992). Teoría de la acción comunicativa. Madrid: Taurus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Handy, R. (1959). The genetic fallacy and naturalistic ethics. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy, 2, 25–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1967). The genetic fallacy revisited. American Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 101–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs, 45, 103–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, C. T. (1990). A critique of genealogies. Metaphilosophy, 21, 391–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleiman, L. (1970). Pashman on freud and the genetic fallacy. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 8, 63–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klement, K. C. (2002). When is genetic reasoning not fallacious? Argumentation, 16, 383–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1974). The role of crucial experiments in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 4, 309–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lavine, T. Z. (1962). Reflections on the genetic fallacy. Social Research, 29, 321–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N. (2003). Analytic and continental philosophy: Explaining the differences. Metaphilosophy, 34, 284–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • López, F. E. (2015). Filosofía y falacias: el caso de la argumentación por las consecuencias en la filosofía pragmatista. X Jornadas de Investigación del Departamento de Filosofía, FaHCE UNLP.

    Google Scholar 

  • López, F. E. (2018). Ética y falacias: para no bloquear el camino de la investigación. Seminario Internacional de Estudios sobre Discurso y Argumentación (SEDiAr), 14 al 16 de Marzo. Instituto de Lingüística (FFyL, UBA) y Universidad Estaual de Santa Cruz (UESC). Inédito.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monk, R. (1996). Bertrand Russell: The spirit of solitude. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pashman, J. (1970). Is the genetic fallacy a fallacy? Southern Journal of Philosophy, 8, 57–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C. (1979). The new rhetoric and the humanities: Essays on rhetoric and its applications. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1969). The new rhetoric. A treatise on argumentation (Trans.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. (Original work published in 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  • Roll-Hansen, N. (1989). The crucial experiment of Wilhelm Johannsen. Biology and Philosophy, 4, 303–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1973). Logic. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2010). Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse, extending the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Garssen, B., & Meuffels, B. (2012). Effectiveness through reasonableness: a pragmadialectical perspective: preliminary steps to pragma-dialectical effectiveness research. Argumentation, 26, 33–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Snoeck Henkemans, F. (2017). Argumentation. Analysis and evaluation. New York and London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1998). Ad Hominem arguments. Alabama: University Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1999). Historical origins of argumentum ad consequentiam. Argumentation, 13, 251–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (2010). Genetic fallacy. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology (2nd ed., p. 393). Singapore: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, A. C. (2010). The value of genetic fallacies. Informal Logic, 30, 1–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Federico E. López .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

López, F.E. (2020). Argument Evaluation in Philosophy: Fallacies as Strategic Maneuvering. In: van Eemeren, F., Garssen, B. (eds) From Argument Schemes to Argumentative Relations in the Wild. Argumentation Library, vol 35. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-28367-4_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics