Skip to main content

Equality, Identity and Impartiality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ethical Competencies for Public Leadership
  • 346 Accesses

Abstract

In liberal democratic societies, there is broad agreement that human persons are of equal moral worth and that we should treat one another as equals. Bromell notes that we do not agree, however, on what it means to treat one another equally, above all in the distribution of social goods. This chapter reflects on what equality means; the basis of human equality; why equality matters; what it means to treat one another equally; and equality between persons and groups, including the place of special measures (affirmative action) and measures to redress historical injustices. The proposed resolution for public leadership is to be impartial. This implies equal concern and respect for persons as persons, including the very young, the very old and the profoundly disabled; blocking hegemonic attempts to secure unequal advantage; and open rather than closed impartiality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Jan Scown, in a private communication (May 31, 2019), commented that during negotiations on the UN Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, recognising that “equal” does not mean “the same” simplified things considerably. Discussion could acknowledge people in all our diversity as well as imperatives for public policy that follow from our basic human equality.

  2. 2.

    Waldron (2017, pp. 19–35) explicitly addresses the philosophical racism of Hastings Rashdall (1907), who argued that there are objective and important differences of kind between human beings, and that “sooner or later, the lower Well-being—it may be ultimately the very existence—of countless Chinamen or negroes must be sacrificed that a higher life may be possible for a much smaller number of white men” (cited by Waldron, 2017, p. 22).

  3. 3.

    This idea links to the “best judge” principle discussed in Sect. 4.2.1.

  4. 4.

    See further Swift (2014, pp. 97–99). On equality as a distributive ideal, see Sect. 5.2.2.

  5. 5.

    See further Dworkin (1978, pp. 180–183, 227, 1981a, p. 185); Nagel (1995); and Miller (2001, pp. 231–232).

  6. 6.

    On the relationship between facts and normative principles, see Cohen (2008, Chap. 6). Cohen argues that “if any facts support any principles, then there are fact-insensitive principles that account for that relationship of support (and, by the same token, if we have any principles at all, then we have fact-insensitive principles)” (pp. 247–248). He clarifies this: “My view that all fact-sensitive principles presuppose fact-insensitive principles doesn’t, then, require that an ‘ought’ can’t follow from an ‘is’. My position is neutral with respect to that dispute…” (p. 249).

  7. 7.

    Metaphysics is logical analysis of unconditionally necessary (a priori) truths. Waldron (2017) himself does not go this far. He does discuss and commend a religious (Anglican Christian) basis for equality (pp. 175–214) and states that human worth and dignity have to be rooted in something like a theological anthropology. His line of argument is important because it hints at the sort of metaphysics we need to complete it, without falling back on the affirmation of beliefs and commitments that not everyone shares. His account of the basis of human equality could, I think, be completed by a transcendental metaphysics of the neoclassical sort capable of distinguishing existence and actuality. See, for example, Whitehead (1978); Hartshorne (1934, 1953, 1962, 1987a, 1987b); Ogden (2018, pp. 141–222); and Gamwell (1990, 2000, 2012). A neoclassical metaphysics has the further advantage of being able to address continuities and discontinuities between humans and the other creatures who share our planet—Waldron’s (2017) principles of continuous and distinctive equality (pp. 30–31). See, for example, Hartshorne (1962, 1968); and Birch (1990, 1991, 1993a, 1993b, 1995, 1999).

  8. 8.

    On supervenience, see Hare (1952, pp. 80ff., 1984); McPherson (2015).

  9. 9.

    Waldron (2017, p. 112) explains that while there is some consonance between his emphasis on capabilities as the properties that ground human equality and the capabilities approach of Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum, he is not invoking capabilities as a currency of justice. Rather, he is singling out a smaller set of capabilities as a basis for our equal worth. See further Nussbaum (2006).

  10. 10.

    Waldron here explicitly addresses (pp. 237–247) Peter Singer’s rejection of a principle of distinctive equality that places a different (and higher) moral value on human beings than non-human animals.

  11. 11.

    Raz (1986) explains: “… what makes us care about various inequalities is not the inequality but the concern identified by the underlying principle. It is the hunger of the hungry, the need of the needy, the suffering of the ill, and so on. The fact that they are worse off in the relevant respect than their neighbours is relevant. But it is relevant not as an independent evil of inequality. Its relevance is in showing that their hunger is greater, their need more pressing, their suffering more hurtful, and therefore our concern for the hungry, the needy, the suffering, and not our concern for equality, makes us give them the priority” (p. 240).

  12. 12.

    Dworkin (2000) reminds us that in totalitarian dictatorships private citizens have equal political power (none), and authoritarian governments and pseudo-democracies may scrupulously ensure one person, one vote (but only for a single party). He argues that “any adequate theory of political equality must compare political power along two dimensions: not only horizontally, by comparing the power of different private citizens or groups of citizens, but also vertically, by comparing the power of private citizens with individual officials” (pp. 190–191).

  13. 13.

    On “luck egalitarianism” and the distinction between brute and option luck, see Dworkin (1981b); Cohen (1989); Anderson (1999); and Scheffler (2003).

  14. 14.

    On equality, choice and expensive tastes, see Scanlon (1975); Dworkin (1981a, 2004); Rawls (1982 pp. 167–170); Cohen (1989, 2004); and Kymlicka (1989, p. 186, 2002, pp. 72–75).

  15. 15.

    My discussion in this section is concerned with identity politics within the nation state. Citizenship is also a form of group identity that a state may use to differentiate access to certain rights and privileges within its borders; for example, access to state-funded services and the right to vote.

  16. 16.

    On recognition and special rights, see also Taylor (1994); and Kymlicka (1995, 1997, 1998, 2001, 2002, Chap. 8).

  17. 17.

    As noted in Sect. 5.1, Fukuyama (2018a) distinguishes thymos (the craving for recognition of dignity), isothymia (the demand to be respected on an equal basis with other people); and megalothymia (the desire to be recognised as superior to others in some respect).

  18. 18.

    Sometimes we talk about this as the difference between equality and equity, where equity has the sense of proportional equality in the distribution of costs and benefits, taking account of factors such as age, needs, luck, agreements (for example, treaties), merit, effort and contribution (Bromell, 2017, p. 106; Duclos, 2006). See further Sect. 6.2.3.2.

  19. 19.

    An exception to this might be special measures to compensate for permanent impairment that persistently and demonstrably compromises social equality, equal basic liberties and equality before the law.

  20. 20.

    Lindsey MacDonald (2016) comments, contra Waldron: “In 20 years of researching indigenous claims, and in a very thorough study of a database of minorities across the world with claims against states [the Minorities at Risk Data Set, Center for International Development and Conflict Management at the University of Maryland], I have never found a statement by an indigenous political actor that they wish for everything to be returned to how it was before colonisation” (pp. 120–121).

  21. 21.

    Arrian of Nicomedia, The Anabasis of Alexander; or, The history of the wars and conquests of Alexander the Great (Book VII, Chap. I), written in the second century CE. See also Sen (2005, p. 15).

  22. 22.

    Open impartiality implies evaluative pluralism—our rational judgments will not necessarily converge and “yield a single, uniquely rational, determinate answer”. Attempting to show that the moral demands we make on others are uniquely rational (closed impartiality) may in fact “be just a way of pushing others around” (Gaus, 2010, p. 64).

  23. 23.

    On impartiality as a requirement of fairness, see further Sect. 6.2.2.1.

References

  • Anderson, E. (1999). What is the point of equality? Ethics, 109(2), 287–337. https://doi.org/10.1086/233897

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1961). What is freedom? In Between past and future: Six exercises in political thought (pp. 143–171). London: Faber and Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R. (1993). Equality. In R. Goodin & P. Pettit (Eds.), A companion to contemporary political philosophy (pp. 489–507). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R. (1995). Against “complex” equality. In D. Miller & M. Walzer (Eds.), Pluralism, justice, and equality (pp. 226–252). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (1995a). Justice as impartiality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (1995b). Spherical justice and global injustice. In D. Miller & M. Walzer (Eds.), Pluralism, justice, and equality (pp. 67–80). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (2001). Culture and equality: An egalitarian critique of multiculturalism. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (2005). Why social justice matters. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, B. (1990). On purpose. Kensington, NSW: New South Wales University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, C. (1991). Chance, purpose, and the order of nature. In C. Birch, W. Eakin, & J. McDaniel (Eds.), Liberating life: Contemporary approaches to ecological theology (pp. 182–200). Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, C. (1993a). Confronting the future: Australia and the world—The next hundred years. Ringwood, VIC: Penguin Australia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, C. (1993b). Regaining compassion for humanity and nature. St. Louis, MO: Chalice Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, C. (1995). Feelings. Sydney: University of New South Wales Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, C. (1999). Biology and the riddle of life. Sydney: University of New South Wales Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boston, J. (2013). What kind of equality matters? In M. Rashbrooke (Ed.), Inequality: A New Zealand crisis (pp. 70–86). Wellington, NZ: Bridget Williams Books.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Boston, J., & Mladenovic, A. (2010). Political equality and the regulation of election spending by parallel campaigners. Australian Journal of Political Science, 45(4), 623–642. https://doi.org/10.1080/10361146.2010.517178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bromell, D. (2017). The art and craft of policy advising: A practical guide. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Callister, P. (2007). Special measures to reduce ethnic disadvantage in New Zealand: An examination of their role. Wellington: Institute of Policy Studies, Victoria University of Wellington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, T. (2006). Rights: A critical introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casal, P. (2007). Why sufficiency is not enough. Ethics, 117(2), 296–326. https://doi.org/10.1086/510692

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. (1989). On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics, 99(4), 906–944. https://doi.org/10.1086/293126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. (2004). Expensive taste rides again. In J. Burley (Ed.), Dworkin and his critics, with replies by Dworkin (pp. 3–29). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. (2008). Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Duclos, J.-Y. (2006). Equity and equality. Discussion paper 2284. Bonn: Institute for the Study of Labor. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.iza.org/publications/dp/2284

  • Dworkin, R. (1978). Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1981a). What is equality? Part 1: Equality of welfare. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10(3), 185–246. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/2264894

  • Dworkin, R. (1981b). What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10(4), 283–345. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/2265047

  • Dworkin, R. (1985). A matter of principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign virtue: The theory and practice of equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2004). Reply to G.A Cohen. In J. Burley (Ed.), Dworkin and his critics, with replies by Dworkin (pp. 339–350). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, A. (2018). Law and society in a populist age: Balancing individual rights and the common good. Bristol: Bristol University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1973). Social philosophy. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1987). Equality as a moral ideal. Ethics, 98(1), 21–43. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/2381290

  • Frankfurt, H. (1997). Equality and respect. Social Research, 64(1), 3–15. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/40971156

  • Fukuyama, F. (2018a). Identity: Contemporary identity politics and the struggle for recognition. London: Profile Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama, F. (2018b). The rise of populist nationalism. In The future of politics (pp. 7–12). Credit Suisse Research Institute, 2018 Davos edition. Zürich: Credit Suisse. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.credit-suisse.com/corporate/en/articles/news-and-expertise/francis-fukuyama-the-rise-of-populist-nationalism-201801.html

  • Gamwell, F. (1990). The divine good: Modern moral theory and the necessity of God. San Francisco, CA: Harper San Francisco.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gamwell, F. (2000). Democracy on purpose: Justice and the reality of God. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gamwell, F. (2012). Existence and the good: Metaphysical necessity in morals and politics. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2010). The demands of impartiality and the evolution of morality. In B. Feltham & J. Cottingham (Eds.), Partiality and impartiality: Morality, special relationships, and the wider world (pp. 42–64). Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199579952.003.0003

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gosepath, S. (2011). Equality. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 ed.). Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/equality/

  • Gutmann, A. (1995). Justice across the spheres. In D. Miller & M. Walzer (Eds.), Pluralism, justice, and equality (pp. 99–119). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. (1952). The language of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. (1984). Supervenience. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 58(1), 1–16. https://doi.org/10.1093/aristoteliansupp/58.1.1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1934). The philosophy and psychology of sensation. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1953). Reality as social process: Studies in metaphysics and religion. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1962). The logic of perfection and other essays in neoclassical metaphysics. LaSalle, IL: Open Court Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1968). Beyond humanism: Essays in the philosophy of nature. Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1987a). Creative synthesis and philosophic method. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne, C. (1987b). Wisdom as moderation: A philosophy of the middle way. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukathas, C. (1992a). Are there any cultural rights? Political Theory, 20(1), 105–139. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/191781

  • Kukathas, C. (1992b). Cultural rights again: A rejoinder to Kymlicka. Political Theory, 20(4), 674–680. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/191974

  • Kymlicka, W. (1989). Liberalism, community, and culture. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (1995). Multicultural citizenship: A liberal theory of minority rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (1997). Do we need a liberal theory of minority rights? Reply to Carens, Young, Parekh and Forst. Constellations, 4(1), 72–87. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-8675.00038

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (1998). Finding our way: Rethinking ethnocultural relations in Canada. Toronto: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (2001). Politics in the vernacular: Nationalism, multiculturalism and citizenship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kymlicka, W. (2002). Contemporary political philosophy: An introduction (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacDonald, L. (2016). Decolonisation starts in a name: Moving on from the colonial pretence that “Māori” or “indigenous peoples” are explanatory frames. Political Science, 68(2), 105–123. https://doi.org/10.1177/0032318716675654

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacDonald, M. (1984). Natural rights. In J. Waldron (Ed.), Theories of rights (pp. 21–40). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Originally published in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 47 (1947), 225–250. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/4544427

  • McPherson, T. (2015). Supervenience in ethics. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2015 Edition). Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/supervenience-ethics/

  • Miller, D. (1995a). Introduction. In D. Miller & M. Walzer (Eds.), Pluralism, justice, and equality (pp. 1–16). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1995b). Complex equality. In D. Miller & M. Walzer (Eds.), Pluralism, justice, and equality (pp. 197–225). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2001). Principles of social justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1979). Equality. In Mortal questions (pp. 106–127). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1995). Equality and partiality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and utopia. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2006). Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, species membership. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogden, S. (2018). Notebooks. Eugene, OR: Cascade Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okun, A. (1975). Equality and efficiency: The big tradeoff. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1995). Equality or priority. The Lindley Lecture. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1997). Equality and priority. Ratio, 10(3), 202–221. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9329.00041

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (1997). Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rashbrooke, M. (2013). Why inequality matters. In M. Rashbrooke (Ed.), Inequality: A New Zealand crisis (pp. 1–17). Wellington, NZ: Bridget Williams Books.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rashdall, H. (1907). The theory of good and evil: A treatise on moral philosophy. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1982). Social unity and primary goods. In A. Sen & B. Williams (Eds.), Utilitarianism and beyond (pp. 159–185). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. E. Kelly (Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Royal Commission on Social Security. (1972). Social security in New Zealand: Report of the Royal Commission of Inquiry. Wellington, NZ: Government Printer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rustin, M. (1995). Equality in post-modern times. In D. Miller & M. Walzer (Eds.), Pluralism, justice, and equality (pp. 17–44). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (1997). Picking winners. The New Republic, 217(22), 13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (2005). Public philosophy: Essays on morality in politics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (2012). What money can’t buy: The moral limits of markets. New York: Farrar, Strauss & Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (1975). Preference and urgency. Journal of Philosophy, 72(19), 655–699. https://doi.org/10.2307/2024630

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (2003). What is egalitarianism? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31(1), 5–39. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/3558033

  • Sen, A. (1995). Equality of what? In A. Sen (Ed.), Inequality re-examined (pp. 12–30). Published to Oxford Scholarship Online, November 2003. https://doi.org/10.1093/0198289286.001.0001

  • Sen, A. (2005). The argumentative Indian: Writings on Indian history, culture and identity. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1776). Wealth of nations. Hoboken, NJ: Generic NL Freebook Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1790). The theory of moral sentiments (rev. ed.), R. Hanley (Ed.). New York: Penguin, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J. (2012). The price of inequality. London: Allen Lane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swift, A. (2014). Political philosophy: A beginners’ guide for students and politicians (3rd ed.). Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1994). The politics of recognition. In A. Gutmann (Ed.), Multiculturalism: Examining the politics of recognition (pp. 25–73). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tobin, J. (1970). On limiting the domain of inequality. Journal of Law and Economics, 13(2), 263–277. https://doi.org/10.1086/466693

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vlastos, G. (1984). Justice and equality. In J. Waldron, (Ed.), Theories of rights (pp. 41–76). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Originally published in R. Brandt (Ed.), Social justice (pp. 31–72). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vonnegut, K., Jr. (1961). Harrison Bergeron. Originally published in The magazine of fantasy and science fiction. Accessed June 5, 2019, from The Internet Archive, https://archive.org/stream/HarrisonBergeron/Harrison%20Bergeron_djvu.txt

  • Waldron, J. (1992). Superseding historic injustice. Ethics, 103(1), 4–28. https://doi.org/10.1086/293468

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (1995). Money and complex equality. In D. Miller & M. Walzer (Eds.), Pluralism, justice, and equality (pp. 144–170). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (2002). Redressing historic injustice. University of Toronto Law Journal, 52(1), 135–160. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.jstor.org/stable/825930

  • Waldron, J. (2012). Dignity, rank, & rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (2017). One another’s equals: The basis of human equality. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice: A defense of pluralism and equality. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. (1978). Process and reality: An essay in cosmology. Corrected ed., D. Griffin & D. Sherburne (Eds.). New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, R., & Pickett, K. (2010). The spirit level: Why equality is better for everyone. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winston, K. (2003). Moral competence in the practice of democratic governance. In J. Donahue & J. Nye Jr. (Eds.), For the people: Can we fix public service? (pp. 169–187). Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winston, K. (2010). Moral competence in public life. SSA/ANZSOG Occasional Paper, 4. Melbourne: ANZSOG. Accessed June 5, 2019, from https://www.anzsog.edu.au/resource-library/research/moral-competence-in-public-life

  • Young, I. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Bromell, D. (2019). Equality, Identity and Impartiality. In: Ethical Competencies for Public Leadership. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-27943-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics