Skip to main content

Philosophy as Education in Thinking: Why Getting the Reader to Think Matters to Wittgenstein

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 714 Accesses

Part of the book series: The Frontiers Collection ((FRONTCOLL))

Abstract

Wittgenstein writes in the preface to the Philosophical Investigations: ‘I should not like my writing to spare other people the trouble of thinking. But if possible, to stimulate someone to thoughts of his own.’ In the following I argue that this indicates something essential about Wittgenstein’s approach. In order to remain true to his conception of philosophy without theses, he could not, for example, aim to instruct his reader about about grammar or put forward prescriptions about grammar, logic or language use. Thus, there is an essential connection between the aim of stimulating the reader to thoughts of their own, and philosophizing without theses. In order to clarify this I will discuss both Wittgenstein’s early and later account of philosophy without theses, his later rejection of philosophical foundations and the hierarchical organization of philosophy, such as assumed in his early philosophy, the notion of agreement in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy, and certain remarks from the Nachlass on the composition of his book, eventually published as the Philosophical Investigations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Although Russell does not explicitly speak about informing anyone in the quote, Russellian philosophical logic is meant to result in true propositions regarding logical forms, thus placing the statements of logic in the same category as those of science (OKEW, 66–67).

  2. 2.

    For an account of the function of the sentences of the Tractatus as intended to introduce logical concepts and principles constitutive of a logical notation, see Kuusela 2019, Chaps. 2 and 3.

  3. 3.

    Possibly the reason why Wittgenstein changed his terminology was simply that around this time, in the early 1930s, Carnap and other logically oriented philosophers started using the term ‘metalogic’ in a different way, as referring to concepts and principles articulated in a metalanguage. However, I am not aware of any comments by Wittgenstein on this issue.

  4. 4.

    These two conceptions of language correspond to the senses in which language is, according to Wittgenstein, both arbitrary and non-arbitrary, as explained in PI §492. Different variants of Wittgenstein’s methods are discussed in Kuusela (2019, Chaps. 4–6).

  5. 5.

    Wittgenstein’s view seems in this respect reminiscent of Kant who famously said that it is not possible to teach philosophy (in the sense of philosophical doctrines), only philosophizing.

References

  • Frege, Gottlob. Posthumous Writings. Hermes, H., Kambartel F., Kaulbach, F. eds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979 (PW).

    Google Scholar 

  • Glock, Hans-Johan. “Philosophical Investigations Section 128: ‘Theses in Philosophy’ and Undogmatic Procedure”. In Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, Text and Context, eds. Arrington, R. L. & Glock, H.-J. London: Routledge, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, Peter. ‘Philosophy’. In Glock, H.-J. ed., Wittgenstein: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuusela, Oskari. ‘Wittgenstein’s Critical Inheritance and Development of Russell’s Logic’, in Klement, K. The Oxford Handbook of Russell. Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuusela, Oskari. The Struggle against Dogmatism: Wittgenstein and the Concept of Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2008a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuusela, Oskari. ‘Transcendental Arguments and the Problem of Dogmatism’. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, Vol. 16, No. 1, pp. 57–75, 2008b.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuusela, Oskari. ‘The Development of Wittgenstein’s Philosophy’, in Kuusela O. and McGinn M. eds., The Oxford Handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuusela, Oskari. Wittgenstein on Logic as the Method of Philosophy: Re-examining the Roots and Development of Analytic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuusela, Oskari. ‘On Wittgenstein’s and Carnap’s Conceptions of the Dissolution of Philosophical Problems, and against a Therapeutic Mix: How to Solve the Paradox of the Tractatus’, Philosophical Investigations, 2019a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. Our Knowledge of the External World. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1926 (OKEW).

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, Bertrand. The Principles of Mathematics. London: Routledge, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1951 (TLP).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge 1939. Diamond, Cora ed. Hassock, Sussex: Harvester Press, 1976 (LFM).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge 1932–35. Ambrose, Alice ed. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979a (AWL).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Notebooks 1914–16. Oxford: Blackwell, 1979b (NB).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Remarks on Colour. Oxford: Blackwell, 1979c (RC).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. ‘Lectures on the Freedom of the Will’. In Klagge, James and Nordmann, Alfred eds., Philosophical Occasions 1912–1951. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Ludwig Wittgenstein: Cambridge Letters, Correspondence with Russell, Keynes, Moore, Ramsey and Straffa. G.H. Von Wright and Brian McGuinness eds. Oxford: Blackwell, 1997 (CL).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Culture and Value. Revised Edition. Oxford: Blackwell, 1998 (CV).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition. Edited by The Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000 (References by manuscript or typescript number).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell-Wiley, 2009 (PI).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper was presented in a philosophy of education seminar at the University College London, Institute of Education in December 2017. I would like to thank those present for their questions and comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Oskari Kuusela .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kuusela, O. (2020). Philosophy as Education in Thinking: Why Getting the Reader to Think Matters to Wittgenstein. In: Wuppuluri, S., da Costa, N. (eds) WITTGENSTEINIAN (adj.). The Frontiers Collection. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-27569-3_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics