Skip to main content

Modal Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Arabic Logic from al-Fārābī to Averroes

Part of the book series: Studies in Universal Logic ((SUL))

  • 494 Accesses

Abstract

Let us start by al-Fārābī’s classification of the modal propositions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See ([76]) for the symbols and the equivalences. I have introduced these modern symbols for convenience. These modern symbols can be found in [49] and [96], for instance.

  2. 2.

    On the modal Octagon of Buridan see [124]. On Buridan’s logic in general see [47], [101], and [103]. On Medieval logic, see [106] and on Medieval modal logic see [104].

  3. 3.

    See S. Chatti ([55], 45–71), for a full analysis of these modal propositions.

  4. 4.

    See Chatti [56] in [117] for a full analysis of these propositions and their relations.

  5. 5.

    See ([53], 339–340), for a full analysis of these tables and these relations.

  6. 6.

    See ([53], 332–353).

  7. 7.

    Here what should be written is “neg. necess” instead of “neg. assert” (see [29], 126, and [30], 100).

  8. 8.

    For an account of the conversions in some of Avicenna’s followers, see [140].

  9. 9.

    Here, there is an error in the text, for what is written is “necessarily every B is A.” Thus written, the letters B and A are not in their right places, given that Baroco is a mood of the second figure, i.e., the figure PP; so B is the middle term, and the premise should be rather “necessarily every A is B,” as we have written.

  10. 10.

    See, for instance, Riccardo Strobino in his recent article ([142], Sect. 3.1).

  11. 11.

    Here there is an error in the text, for what is written is “described as B only.” However the right letter should be C, since C is the subject of the proposition.

  12. 12.

    Note here that he does not say “ḍarūrīyya sāliba”, which would be translated by “necessary negative”, but rather “ḍarūrīyyata al-salb”, which I have translated as “necessarily negative.”

  13. 13.

    Even Ip (= I permanent) leads to Iga

  14. 14.

    Here, there is an error of editing since what is written is that “the major premise is a universal necessary negative” ([34], 157.13, my emphasis). But this could not be so, since the mood Ferison is the ninth mood and will be presented and developed by Avicenna at page 158.

  15. 15.

    See Saloua Chatti ([55]), where it is shown that the possible propositions too have an existential import.

  16. 16.

    Here there is an error in the text, not noted by the editor, for what is written is that the minor premise is absolute, but this could not be so, since the conversion leads to a possible minor premise, which with the absolute major leads to an absolute conclusion. Furthermore, the case of the mood with an absolute minor is considered just after the first one, in the sequel, where Avicenna says “If the minor is absolute, then the conclusion is a bilateral possible” ([34], 225.7)

  17. 17.

    With regard to Aristotle’s opinion about the modalities see, for instance, Marko Malink who says in his article “A reconstruction of Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic” ([113]) the following: “In Aristotle’s modal syllogistic, however, there are no iterable modal sentential operators and, as a consequence, no de dicto modalities.” ([113], 96)

References

  1. Al-Fārābī, Abū Naṣr. 1960. Şharh al-Fārābī li kitāb Arisṭūṭālīs fī al-ʻIbāra, ed. Wilhelm Kutch and Stanley Marrow, 2nd edn. Beirut: Dar el-Mashriq.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Al-Fārābī, Abū Naṣr. 1986. Kitāb al-‘Ibāra. In al-Manṭiq ‘inda al-Fārābī, vol. 1, ed. Rafik Al Ajam, pp. 133–64. Beirut: Dar el Machriq.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Al-Fārābī, Abū Naṣr. 1988. al-Qawl fī al-ʻIbāra, in al-Manṭiqiyāt li-al-Fārābi, vol. 1, texts published by Mohamed Teki Danesh Pazuh, Edition Qom, pp. 83–114.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Al-Fārābī, Abū Naṣr. 1988. Sharh al-‘Ibāra. in al-Manṭiqiyāt li-al-Farābi, vol. 2, texts published by Mohamed Teki Danesh Pazuh, Edition Qom, 1409 of Hegira.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Al-Fārābī, Abū Naṣr. 1988. Kitāb al Qiyās. In al-Manṭiqiyāt li-al-Fārābi, vol. 1, texts published by Mohamed Teki Danesh Pazuh, Edition Qom, 115–151.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Al-Fārābī, Abū Naṣr. 1988. Mā yanbaghī an yuqaddama qabla ta‛allum al-falsafa. In al-Mantiqiyyāt li-al-Fārābī, texts published by Mohamed Teki Danesh Pazuh, Edition Qom, pp. 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Aristotle. 1991. Prior analytics. In The Complete Works of Aristotle, ed. Jonathan Barnes, vol. 1, the Revised Oxford edn.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Averroes. 1982. Talkhīṣ Manṭiq Arisṭu (Paraphrase de la logique d’Aristote), volume 1: Kitāb Al-Maqūlāt (pp. 3–77), Kitāb al-‘Ibāra (pp. 81–141), Kitāb al-Qiyās (pp. 143–366), ed. Gérard Jehamy, Manshūrāt al-Jāmi‛a al-lubnānīya, al-Maktaba al-sharqiyya, Beirut.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Averroes. 1983. Middle commentary on Aristotle’s prior analytics, Critical edition by M. Kassem, completed, revised and annotated by C. E. Butterworth, and A. Abd al-Magid Haridi, Cairo.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Averroes. 1983. Maqālāt fī al-manṭiq wa-al-ʻilm al-ṭabīʻī [Essays on logic and natural science], ed. Jamāl al-Dīn al-ʻAlawī. Casablanca.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Averroes. 2001. Kitāb al-Muqaddamāt fi al-Falsafa, al-Masāʼil fi-al Manṭiq wa al ʻilm al-ṭabīʻī wa al-Ṭibb, ed. Assad Jemaa. Tunis: Markez al-Nashr al-Jāmiʻī.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Avicenna. 1938. al-Najāt, Muḥyi al-Dīn Sabrī al-Kurdī, 2nd edn. Cairo: Library Mustapha al Bab al Hilbi.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Avicenna. 1964. al-Shifā’, al-Manṭiq 4: al-Qiyās, ed. S. Zayed, rev. and intr. by I. Madkour, Cairo.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Avicenna. 1970. al-Shifā’, al-Manṭiq 3: al-‘Ibāra, ed. M. El Khodeiri, rev. and intr. by I. Madkour, Cairo.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Avicenna. 1971. Al-Ishārāt wa l–tanbīhāt, with the commentary of N. Ṭūsi, intr by Dr. Seliman Donya, Part 1, 3rd edn. Cairo: Dar al Ma’arif.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Bäck, Allan. 1992. Avicenna’s conception of the modalities. Vivarium XXX (2): 217–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Badawi, Abderrahman. 1980. Manṭiq Arisṭu, vol. 1 and 2. Beirut: Dar al Kalam.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Buridan, Jean. 1985. Jean Buridan’s logic, the treatise on supposition, the treatise on consequences, trans. P. King. Dordrecht and Holland: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Carnap, Rudolf. 1988. Meaning and necessity, a study in semantics and modal logic, 2nd edn. Chicago and London: Midway Reprint Edition, The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Chatti, Saloua. 2014. Avicenna on possibility and necessity. History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (4): 332–353.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. Chatti, Saloua. 2016. Existential import in Avicenna’s modal logic. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 26 (1): 45–71. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Chatti, Saloua. 2016. Les oppositions modales dans la logique d’al-Fārābī. In Soyons logiques / Let’s be Logical, ed. Amirouche Moktefi, Alessio Moretti, and Fabien Schang. Collection: Cahiers de logique et d’épistémologie (ed. Shahid Rahman and Dov Gabbay). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Dadkhah, Gholamreza, and Asadollah Fallahi. 2018. Logic in 6th/12th century Iran (Arabic texts with Persian notes and English introduction). Tehran: Iranian Institute of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Elamrani-Jamal, Abdelali. 1995. Ibn Rušd et les Premiers Analytiques d’Aristote: Aperçu sur un problème de syllogistique modale. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 5: 51–74.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  25. Garson, James. 2018. Modal logic. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-modal/.

  26. Hasnawi, Ahmed, and Wilfrid Hodges. 2016. Arabic logic up to Avicenna. In The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Logic, ed. Catarina Dutilh Novaes and Stephen Read, pp. 45–66. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  27. Hodges, Wilfrid. Ibn Sina: Qiyas ii.3, translation based on the Cairo text, ed. Ibrahim Madhkur et al. Draft. http://wilfridhodges.co.uk/arabic21.pdf.

  28. Hughes, George Edward, and M.J. Cresswell. 1972. An introduction to modal logic. London: Methuen and Co. Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  29. King, Peter. 1985. Introduction to Jean Buridan’s logic. In Jean Buridan’s logic. D. Reidel: Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Klima, Gyula, John Buridan: His nominalist logic, metaphysics, and epistemology. Great Medieval Thinkers. Oxford University Press. http://www.phil-inst.hu/~gyula/FILES/John-Buridan.pdf.

  31. Knuutila, Simo. 2008. Medieval theories of modalities. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/modality-medieval/.

  32. Lagerlund, Henrik. 2010. Medieval theories of the syllogism. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.standord.edu/entries/medieval-syllogism/.

  33. Malink, Marko. 2006. A reconstruction of Aristotle’s modal syllogistic. History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (2): 95–141.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  34. Moktefi, A., A. Moretti, and F. Schang (eds.). 2016. Let’s be logical. London: College Publications.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  35. Movahed, Zia. 2010. De re and de dicto modality in the Islamic traditional logic. Sophia Perennis 2 (2): 5–19.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Movahed, Zia. 2017. Ibn-Sīnā’s anticipation of the formulas of Buridan and Barcan. In Logic in Tehran, ed. Ali Enayat et al., pp. 248–255. Wellesley, MA: Association for Symbolic Logic and A. K. Peters. First edition (2003).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Read, Stephen. 2012. The medieval theory of consequence. Synthese 187: 899–912.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  38. Street, Tony. 2014. Afḍal al-Dīn al-Khunājī (d. 1248) on the conversion of modal propositions. ORIENS 42: 454–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Strobino, Riccardo. 2018. Ibn Sīnā’s logic. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/ibn-sina-logic.

  40. Thom, Paul. 2008. al-Fārābī on indefinite and privative names. Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 18 (2): 193–209.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  41. Thom, Paul. 2008. Logic and metaphysics in Avicenna’s modal syllogistic. In The Unity of Science in the Arabic tradition, ed. Shahid Rahman, Tony Street, and Hassen Tahiri, pp. 361–376. Dordrecht.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Saloua Chatti .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Chatti, S. (2019). Modal Logic. In: Arabic Logic from al-Fārābī to Averroes . Studies in Universal Logic. Birkhäuser, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-27466-5_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics